Qualitative Research Journal
The et hics of nobody I know: gender and t he polit ics of descript ion
Laurie Timothy
Article information:
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
To cite this document:
Laurie Timothy , (2014),"The ethics of nobody I know: gender and the politics of description", Qualitative
Research Journal, Vol. 14 Iss 1 pp. 64 - 78
Permanent link t o t his document :
http://dx.doi.org/10.1108/QRJ-03-2014-0011
Downloaded on: 21 August 2014, At : 16:38 (PT)
References: t his document cont ains references t o 43 ot her document s.
To copy t his document : permissions@emeraldinsight .com
The fullt ext of t his document has been downloaded 27 t imes since 2014*
Access t o t his document was grant ed t hrough an Emerald subscript ion provided by 472570 []
For Authors
If you would like t o writ e for t his, or any ot her Emerald publicat ion, t hen please use our Emerald for
Aut hors service informat ion about how t o choose which publicat ion t o writ e for and submission guidelines
are available for all. Please visit www.emeraldinsight .com/ aut hors for more informat ion.
About Emerald www.emeraldinsight.com
Emerald is a global publisher linking research and pract ice t o t he benefit of societ y. The company
manages a port folio of more t han 290 j ournals and over 2,350 books and book series volumes, as well as
providing an ext ensive range of online product s and addit ional cust omer resources and services.
Emerald is both COUNTER 4 and TRANSFER compliant. The organization is a partner of the Committee
on Publication Ethics (COPE) and also works with Portico and the LOCKSS initiative for digital archive
preservation.
*Relat ed cont ent and download informat ion correct at t ime of download.
The current issue and full text archive of this journal is available at
www.emeraldinsight.com/1443-9883.htm
QRJ
14,1
The ethics of nobody I know:
gender and the politics of
description
64
Timothy Laurie
Cultural Studies, The University of Melbourne, Melbourne, Australia
Abstract
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
Purpose – This paper aims to bring together feminist philosophy, phenomenology, and masculinity
studies to consider the gendered formation of ethical practices, focusing on the construction of “male”
and “female” identities in quotidian social encounters. While scholarship on masculinity has
frequently focused on hegemonic modes of behaviour or normative gender relations, less attention has
been paid to the “ethics of people I know” as informal political resources, ones that shapes not only
conversations about how one should act (“people I know don’t do that”), but also about the diversity of
situations that friends, acquaintances or strangers could plausibly have encountered (“that hasn’t
happened to anyone I know”).
Design/methodology/approach – The paper rethinks mundane social securities drawing on
Martin Heidegger, Simone de Beauvoir, and Sara Ahmed to consider anecdotal case studies around
gender recognition and political practice, and in doing so also develops the notion of interpellation in
relation to everyday ethical problems.
Findings – The paper suggests that inquiry into diverse modes of quotidian complicities – or what de
Beauvoir calls the “snares” of a deeply human liberty – can be useful for describing the mixtures
of sympathy, empathy, and disavowal in the performance of pro-feminist and queer-friendly
masculinities or masculinist identities. It also suggests that the adoption of an “anti-normative”
politics is insufficient for negotiating the problems of description and recognition involved in the
articulation of gendered social experiences.
Originality/value – This paper approaches questions around political identification commonly
considered in queer theory from the viewpoint of descriptive practices themselves, and thus reorients
problems of recognition and interpellation towards the expression of ethical statements, rather than
focusing solely on the objects of such statements.
Keywords Masculinity, Politics, Feminism, Norms, Simone de Beauvoir, Queer, Sara Ahmed
Paper type Conceptual paper
Qualitative Research Journal
Vol. 14 No. 1, 2014
pp. 64-78
r Emerald Group Publishing Limited
1443-9883
DOI 10.1108/QRJ-03-2014-0011
Introduction
Crossing the platform at a Melbourne train station some time ago, a woman shot
briskly ahead of me, bag swinging in the rush of fumbled tickets and late arrivals.
Before reaching the stairs, a stranger with a hard masculine stride lurched towards
the woman and, pointing to the ground, said “you dropped something there”. As she
turned to look the man quickly whispered something in her ear and she set off
again – still briskly, perhaps more so. Barely glimpsing the offender’s face, I caught
myself staring instead at the profile of the woman, searching for signs of a disturbance:
anxiety, annoyance, embarrassment, non-chalance, and humiliation. What will be her
response? How will she wear it?
From this fastidious examination emerged a fuzzy description of someone I did not
know, one that combined an affective response with a political orientation. I may have
This paper has benefited from generous and insightful comments provided by Jessica Kean and
Adam Gall.
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
been trying to detect resemblances with a previous occasion where I had known,
or had imagined to have known, how relations between men and women could best
be understood, mediated, or otherwise transformed. And perhaps, chasing after the
woman as a man, I could have reminded her of men who are “not like that” and who
represent a majority “on her side”, converting the fluster of the encounter into a more
tangible moral act.
Alongside feminist-allied men, pro-feminist men and progressive men, the phrase
“male feminist” has been used to overcome simple binaries between patriarchal and
non-patriarchal men, or between masculinity and femininity as immutable character
traits (see Digby, 1998). And indeed, undertones in the anecdote above point to
some version of the male feminist: the narrator might endeavour to be both a man
and a person concerned with feminist politics without much hesitation. Nevertheless,
the phrase “male feminist” suggests several different stories about what having
a gender or doing feminism might mean. First, “male” is no longer understood
as the monolithic biological, psychological, or social category it once was. As
sociologists and anthropologists have frequently shown, gendered self-presentation
can require specialised habits of comportment and etiquette, ways of speaking
and listening, facial expressions, and explicit or implicit acts of naming. Gender
is a vast orchestration of subtle mediations between oneself and others, not a
latent private cause behind manifest behaviours in public. Second, the gendered
modifier – from feminist to male feminist – could support a peculiar myth that
for women “feminism” is an automatic and unthinking political affiliation, while
for men it is an extraordinary moral acquisition. As Rosi Braidotti (2011, pp. 132-133)
points out, the “female feminist subject” is not a default partisan perspective
inherent in “woman” but an intersection of complex desires and social
transformations that exceed any single ideological formulation or identitarian
alliance. Being a feminist can only make sense as a relational and social practice,
even if these relations and practices are sporadic, virtual or otherwise “nomadic”
(see Braidotti, 2011 throughout).
Taken together, “male feminist” suggests some harmonious agreement between
these two kinds of social relationship, one which produces the effect of maleness and
another that produces the effect of participating in, or contributing towards, feminism.
And yet the concept of “men doing feminism” also highlights a disjuncture between the
ideological aspects of political agitation and the actual work of reiterating one’s
identity for a given field of political participation. This tension is most pronounced in
cases where perceived “maleness” attracts particular kinds of political mobility or
institutional comforts, and unfortunately this still describes most cases.
This article examines the entanglement of gender identity and political motivation,
with special attention paid to the vicissitudes of “masculinity” in producing both
positive and negative political identifications. It begins by considering existential
approaches to politics, identification and the everyday, borrowing first from Martin
Heidegger and then focusing on Simone de Beauvoir’s (1949) The Second Sex.
The following section turns to the problems of description raised by de Beauvoir’s
work and considers the relationship between political statements, descriptive
statements, and social norms. Finally, I consider the work of Sara Ahmed, who
in various ways demonstrates that the efficacy of political praxis is shaped by
commitments to the familiar and to practices of familiarisation, raising some distinct
questions about the efficacy of interpellation, and self-description in relation to gender
identity and gender politics.
Politics of
description
65
QRJ
14,1
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
66
Doing the right thing
I began with an anecdote about gender in a public space, not in order to better prove
the argument that now follows but in order to provide what Meaghan Morris calls an
“allegorical exposition” of “a model of the way the world can be said to be working”
(qtd. in Probyn, 1993, p. 11). Later I will discuss the rhetorical effect of the allegory
itself, and in particular, the choices involved in producing a narrator and narrated,
a beginning and an end, through which to analyse an interpellative situation. But I
want to focus first on “pro-feminist” political motivations as described by the narrator,
in order to draw out tensions around what it means to seize a political identity.
Back at the train station: I could have offered the gift of friendship, perhaps through
a pursuit leading to something along the lines of, “men like that are the worst, don’t
you think?”. This would be an interpellation of sorts, but not one resembling
Louis Althusser’s (1971) famous policeman shouting “Hey, you there!” (pp. 171-172).
My pursuit would better resemble Althusser’s second interpellating gesture, “‘Hello,
my friend’, and shaking his hand [y]” (Althusser, 1971, p. 172). The receiver of a
friendly gift would become a friend in distress, while ambiguities around the difference
between myself from the mysterious villain – exact content of crime, unknown – would
be resolved in the political flagging of affiliation and disaffiliation. The crime would
not be my own; as a declaration of friendship would implicitly confirm, the villain was
not someone that I know.
And this might not be a bad thing. The interpellation of others is a structure and not
a sin, and its outcomes are always uncertain. Nevertheless, there are good reasons to
scrutinise potentially gendered modalities of political intervention. One reason is
provided in Martin Heidegger’s commentary on “leaping in”:
[Solicitude] can, as it were, take away “care” from the Other and put itself in his [sic] position
in concern: it can leap in for him. This kind of solicitude takes over for the Other that with
which he is to concern himself. The Other is thus thrown out of his own position; he steps
back so that afterwards, when the matter has been attended to, he can either take it over as
something finished and at his disposal, or disburden of it completely. In such solicitude the
Other can become one who is dominated and dependent, even if this domination is a tacit one
and remains hidden from him (Heidegger, 2008, pp. 122, 158, emphasis in original).
The leaper hopes to mitigate the concerns of others by assuming “their issue” as his
or her responsibility. This requires a displacement of sorts, the adoption of a role that
implicates, or even demands, alternative roles for others – male-offender, woman-indistress, and the irrational unknown Other. There is a possibility that the tenacious
social insistence upon the connection between “femininity” and “womanhood” can be
reaffirmed, in no uncomplicated way, by the type of “leaping in” whereby men seek to
right the wrongs done to women by other men. This could also be called the “possessive
logic” of humanitarianism (see Gall, 2008, pp. 102-103): once a victim becomes unable,
incapable, or inactive, a smorgasbord of condescensions become available to those who
leap in. As a role and as a narrative, heroism is made convincing through the exhibition
of “needy” bodies, or through the reorientation of perception such that some bodies come
to seem intrinsically “needier” than others (Berlant, 1997, pp. 122-123).
The presumed capacity of gender to deliver mundane truths about personal
character can serve a broad constellation of desires well beyond the train station leap.
Consider an example discussed by Riki Wilchins (2002):
As a panel member at a gay journalists’ conference, I wanted to talk about issues, politics,
gender-based hate crimes and job discrimination. But first audience members wanted to
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
know what I “was”. As reporters, they needed a label to identify me to their readers, not to
mention their editors. The predictable questions flew. Did I consider myself transgendered?
Was I presenting myself as male or female? (p. 44).
Wilchins’ example points to the limitations of an emancipatory sexual politics not
coupled with an epistemological and social critique of gender binaries themselves.
The demand that one either present as woman or as man or as a post-operative
transsexual is inseparable from the ubiquitous violence of gender regulation as
quotidian social practice (Wilchins, 2002, pp. 43-44).
However, I want to tease out a different issue here, one connected to the notion of
leaping in. While Wilchins’ focus is rightly on the toxic effects of binary thinking,
it is also notable that binaries can become sedimented as a key mode of political
interpellation for those wanting, claiming, hoping, or demanding to “do the right
thing”. Questioning gender binaries “often engenders vertigo and terror over the
possibility of losing social sanctions, of leaving a solid social station and place” (Butler,
1986, p. 42), and correspondingly, gendered taxonomies can provide fertile resources
for those wanting to feel steady of moral high ground rather than floundering or
free-falling. To “leap in” is to make gender politics a moral venture that fortifies
an epistemology of self and others, one that ostensibly shields the leaper from any
complicated involvement in the situation they seek to modify. The contradictory
situation of social gendering, as both a resisted practice and as a conditioning
possibility for viewing oneself or others as unambiguously politically resistive, can be
resolved through elegant narrative formulations: fighting for women, fighting for men
who love men, and so on. The arrogation of familiar gender signifiers in order to
“do the right thing” can thus unknowingly (but knowingly too) foreclose the promise of
gender activism to challenge social orders dependent on the dimorphisms male/female
and masculine/feminine.
Some brief assistance from contemporary political theory might be useful here.
Prominent philosophers including Ernesto Laclau (2005), Chantal Mouffe (2013),
and Jacques Rancière (1999) have sought to formalise accounts of something that, in a
somewhat austere nominalised form, is called the Political. Chantal Mouffe (2013)
suggests that the formation of political identity always involves “the constitution of
a ‘we’ which requires as its very condition of possibility the demarcation of a ‘they’”
(p. 5), while Jacques Rancière (1999) claims that “politics exists wherever the count of
parts and parties of society is disturbed by the inscription of a part of those who have
no part” (p. 123). Whatever variant of the political one chooses, a consistent theme is
the ineradicability of antagonism or structures of inclusion and exclusion from social
life (for Rancière, 1999, p. xii, “politics” is also “that activity which has the rationality of
disagreement as its very own rationality”). Binaries like masculine/feminine, cis/trans,
hetero/homo do not simply produce poor “representations” of the world; they also
constitute political ontologies wherein a multiplicity of affects, conflicts, and deviations
become possible[1]. Such ontologies are neither uniform nor predictable in their
outcomes: Michael Flood notes that, in addition to possible desires for politically
acceptable forms of group solidarity based on gender, men seeking to actively
construct non-violent masculinities may draw on “concerns for children, intimacies
with women, and ethical and political commitments”, among others (Flood, 2001, p. 45).
Nevertheless, once attached to political projects based on the coherence of such
distinctions, one can also become attached to the social relationships that sustain these
projects. Crude examples might be efforts to interpellate men as “courageous” when
Politics of
description
67
QRJ
14,1
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
68
fighting sexism (consider Cosmo’s 2012 campaign, “Real Men Don’t Hit Women”),
for courage can also be a conspicuously gendered operation for converting assertiveness
and even violence into intrinsic social goods. Similarly, if men pledge “never to commit,
condone or remain silent about (violence against women)” (Flood, 2001, p. 43),
to what extent does this pledge either consolidate or disturb personal commitments to
gender dimorphism? Without wanting to trivialise what are strategically important
statements for shifting a broad discourse on men and violence, it does raise long-term
problems around masculinity and femininity as resources for thinking through
what is just or unjust, especially when one is forced to choose between gender-based
“action”, on the one hand, and challenging the violence of compulsory social gendering,
on the other.
Justice and the everyday
Simone de Beauvoir’s(1949) The Second Sex is hardly a novel touchstone for the issues
discussed here, but does allow certain problems around politics and sex to be posed
with greater precision. In particular, it might be asked whether gender-based “justice”
is a political outcome that individuals can desire separately from all those other wants
that shape social fields of political participation. Certainly, the concept of justice
continues to have clear benefits in activating radical political sensibilities (see Young,
1990, pp. 6-7). An influential and compelling voice in the field, R.W. Connell (2002) has
suggested that social justice could provide a foundation for masculinity studies and
links this to the theme of democracy as a pressing issue for those challenging
hegemonic masculinities.
Nevertheless, justice – like politics – is a prickly concept. For Simone de Beauvoir,
the much touted desire to execute justice on behalf of abstract, intangible, and
selfless humanist ideals is not only implausible but actively deleterious to any complex
understanding of human motivations. Ever wary about the excesses of moralism,
de Beauvoir (1975, pp. 616,627) is disappointed by the claustrophobic reasoning of those
who apply themselves to “a confused conglomeration of special cases”, substituting
opinions about moral actions or personal virtue for the more difficult work of
project-building and the creation of new collective goals. Correspondingly,
future-oriented political gestures always carry with them something of the
irrationality, a-morality and imbalance of their circumstances:
The individual who acts considers himself [sic], like others, as responsible for both evil and
good, he knows that it is for him to define ends, to bring them to success; he becomes aware,
in action, of the ambiguousness of all solutions; justice and injustice, gains and losses, are
inextricably mixed. But anyone who is passive is out of the game and declines to pose ethical
problems even in thought: the good should be realized, and if it is not, there must be some
wrongdoing for which those to blame must be punished. (de Beauvoir, 1975, p. 618, emphasis
in original).
In abandoning the moralistic ideal of a fixed good against which misdeeds are
measured, one must also refuse of facile symmetries between the oppressed and the
oppressor, the victim and the perpetrator, and the right and the wrong. This means, in
turn, rethinking how the “objects” of gender violence are positioned vis-a`-vis gender-based
justice. In a broad reading The Second Sex criticises the liberal notion that justice can be
rationally metered out by persons or institutions themselves shaped, and indeed made
intelligible, through social antagonism and political struggle (de Beauvoir, 1975, p. 732;
see also Moi, 1990, pp. 40-47). But in a narrower sense, de Beauvoir (1975) is
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
particularly critical of the persistent desire of men – not least of all those who
identify as radical men – to see women as weak, a perception that can too
easily reframe “just” acts as simply those that rectify the presumed disadvantages
experienced by those who do not regularly exercise powers of social domination
(pp. 698-699). Thus The Second Sex concludes with the suggestion that “(it) is not
a question of abolishing in woman the contingencies and miseries of the human
condition, but of giving her the means for transcending them” (de Beauvoir, 1975,
p. 736). The politicking of bodies necessarily requires drawing on, modifying, and
transforming the capabilities that “gender” has both extended and foreclosed[2].
Effective action demands caprice and inconstancy in efforts to speak with and against
gender in the same breath, and so one is often likely to find oneself baffled, irritated,
mad, disgusted, or delirious[3].
Gender has an everydayness to it, which is quite a different thing from being
culturally stable or readily cognizable. What matters in The Second Sex is not the
victory of one gender-based ideology over another (although some are more reliable
than others), but how a “total pattern” of everyday life is experienced and practiced
through uneven distributions of action and inaction, visibility and invisibility, and
pleasure and trauma (de Beauvoir, 1975, p. 691). This total pattern has a fuzzy
consistency, structured neither by unconscious laws nor by mysterious forces of
organic social combination, but by a certain regularity that can only be understood
over time, and through the discord of multiple successes and multiple failures. Where
creative writing for women opens doors in one place, it closes them in another; where
free expression announces itself in the female ballet dancer’s pivot, it later forecloses
with unexpected landings (de Beauvoir, 1975, pp. 542-567). The tumble of openings and
closings comprises the “ambiguous situation” of femininity, it is “in the knowledge of
the genuine conditions of our life that we must draw our strength to live and our reason
for acting” (de Beauvoir, 1948, p. 9). An ethical project would be one that develops
and envelops the ambiguity of its particular situation, challenging gender not through
a critique of false knowledge but by creating new ways to inhabit the ambivalences
of the everyday and to make such habitation available to others. Meaghan Morris
(1998) develops this theme further, noting that “(ambivalence) does not eliminate the
moment of everyday discontent – of anger, frustration, sorrow, irritation, hatred,
boredom, fatigue”, and that “(feminism) is minimally a movement of discontent with
‘the everyday’, and with wide-eyed definitions of the everyday as ‘the way things are’”
(p. 69, emphasis in original). This requires a shift from seeking out transgressions
beyond the quotidian to a more sideways-looking interest in the tolerable and
intolerable contradictions of the everyday itself, including the grime and gruel of
habitual complicities with what, despite its now quite disparate connotations, might
still be called phallocentrism.
Unfortunately, while de Beauvoir’s work continues to prompt important critical
questions for liberal approaches to the study of masculinity and femininity, the
answers provided by The Second Sex are not always satisfying. As Susan Best (1999)
notes, concepts like “project” and “activity” must be treated with caution, because this
rhetoric of self-assertion risks over-valorising potentially insensitive or dangerous
social gratifications. Just as importantly, both liberal and existential accounts of gender
liberation can lead to a certain epistemological conservatism, because the politicisation
of social identities can also lead to the over-formalisation of differences between “men”
and “women”, “masculine” and “feminine” bodies, loving the “same sex” and loving
a “different sex”, and so on. Even in reformed existential terms, a woman liberated
Politics of
description
69
QRJ
14,1
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
70
from gender oppression must remain recognisably a “woman” to signify her liberation;
correspondingly, struggles over masculinity and femininity without “liberated men”,
and “liberated women” as cognizable outcomes are ones that must also rethink how
justice might be measured. Feminist scholars such as Luce Irigaray and Judith Butler
have parted ways from Simone de Beauvoir in recognising that while gender
politicking is always forced to begin with contemporary notions of what “man” and
“woman” could or should be, the results of such efforts cannot be entirely anticipated
from within existing epistemologies of gendered self-hood.
Which brings us to the problem of description.
Between politics and description
If there are philosophical reasons why The Second Sex foregrounds the specificity of a
“situation” over liberal conceptions of personhood, these also involve different textual
practices: in particular, a revaluation of narrative, anecdote and prose description as
viable philosophical utensils. Of these forms, description is less often scrutinised than
narrative. Narrative storytelling attaches itself to beginnings and endings, origins that
start with a bang! and conclusions that stick like burnt sugar. As a writer of narratives
one can choose one’s beginnings and endings, backdrops and stage centres, star actors
and minor parts. These choices then re-emerge as imperatives worked into the text itself:
the heroic moral act – the gift, the apology, the defense – can be upheld as an exemplary
remedy to social violence, giving a “nowness” to a tangible economy of harm done and
compensation offered. From a phenomenological viewpoint, however, we never actually
encounter a narrative in its totality. Rather, narrative elements are compiled from
everyday repetitions, whether recurring statements, gestures, social interactions, images
and sounds, recollections and future expectations, among many others. The same
explicitly sexist gesture may pass from a locker room to a political speech to a train
platform. It can be difficult to talk eloquently about gendered violence inflicted not last
Tuesday but often, not just in Melbourne but in too many places, not by the mysterious
villain but by too many people. The bare repetitions of everyday living (“catching
the train”) can contain traces of the disguised repetitions of the not-yet and the
already-happened, the psychic drama lived in, and through the cracks of the quotidian.
In this context, “description” does not refer solely to prose writing or poetry.
There is reason to be sceptical of the distinction between indexical writing that seeks
to produce impressions of particulars, and writing that aspires to be universal in
character and to produce generalisable conclusions. As Moira Gatens (2007) has
recently argued, the classification of literature as a “non-philosophical” genre, or of
philosophy as surpassing the nominalist trappings of literature, has itself been tied
to the gendering of philosophical practice, and in particular, the dismissal of women
writers from the philosophical canon. To say that all writing is inflected by latent
genres of description is to challenge, if only at a formal level, the disciplinary
reification of philosophy as producing more transferable truths than, say, poetry,
cinema, music, or the novella. But description is by no means a redemptive practice; its
capacity to do philosophical work only heightens the diversity of purposes, both
desirable and undesirable, that description might serve. Here I will here pay special
attention to three aspects of description: the hierarchy of elements, the production of an
originary “I”, and the anticipation of readerly responses.
First, as Phillipe Hamon (1982) suggests, a description assumes a particular
referential function that “is interchangeable with, and in certain conditions equivalent
to, a word (a common or proper noun, a name) or a diectic pronoun (him, this, that [y])”
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
(p. 148, emphasis in original). This referential unit has relative semantic autonomy
“independent of its stylistic setting and of the meaning of its constituent elements”
(p. 148), so that all description has a hierarchical aspect. For example, Kath
Woodward’s (2011) study of “affects” in boxing considers “the relationship between
objects, the equipment [y] boxers, trainers, cut men, promoters, commentators and
spectators”, and demonstrates that boxing has “capacity to generate a particular
version of hegemonic masculinity which has considerable purchase among networks
of men” (pp. 492, 501). Despite the heterogeneity of the content included, the author
must begin with the elevation of a unique semantic unit (“boxing”) to narrow the
seemingly infinite world of causes and effects into a readable story about affect(s).
In the Heideggerian patois, description brings forth the “thingyness” of the thing
described.
Second, there is the “I” that authenticates a plausible origin from which
a description could be produced. Sara Ahmed (1998) notes that although “the ‘I’ is
transportable, it does not stay in one place”, and that in much postmodern writing
about gender, the repetition of implied masculine “I”s can suggest “the determination
of an enigma through a gendered modality of address in which woman remains the
object of the naming quest” (p. 132). This complicates my own use of descriptive
anecdote to stage the scene of the crime above: in the “heterosexual exchange which
fixes woman as an enigma for men” (Ahmed, 1998, p. 133, emphasis in original),
the assumed availability of the female body to scrutiny confirms to this gaze that
femininity is, indeed, a thing to be seen.
Finally, there is a normative dialogical structure to descriptive writing. A statement
like “Harry is masculine” not only produces a hierarchy between two terms (the
adjective “masculine” is variable in a way that the inferred existence of a “Harry” is
not), but also says to the reader, “were you to be a normal person meeting Harry under
normal circumstances you should find him to be masculine”. The statement already
presupposes a normative calibration of signifying systems and reading practices, and
an acceptance of “the unhampered freedom of view that is indicated in the text”, which
in turn “authorizes the author’s unhampered description” (Hamon, 1982, p. 149). In the
anecdote with which I began, the text insists that, had they been there, my reader
should have seen a “hard” “masculine” stride in action; or that, at a certain point,
the incident would naturally culminate in a decision between alternatives, and that one
action would be more politically agreeable than another. But this is also why, as I will
later show, the desire to resist norms in some contemporary queer scholarship can
never be entirely reconciled with an equally important challenge, that of producing
both adequate and dynamic descriptions of ordinary events[4].
What is the relationship between descriptive statements and political statements?
Anyone who has ever painted a banner, chanted at a rally, or lost patience arguing over
a topical issue knows that effective political claims demand subtractions. “Enough
Is Enough”, “Just Say No”, “We are The People”: how much can be skinned from
the bare bones of a slogan, how much waste can be culled from a collective chant or
iconic image, while still retaining a tangible referential function? To make a political
statement is to assert a unity of purpose while clearing the space between opposing
purposes. Political antagonism is anti-descriptive, and for this reason political
philosophers rarely claim to describe the political. Judith Butler (1993), for example,
begins Bodies that Matter by insisting that “sex” is not something that can be given any
kind of “static description” (p. xx), and that the “delimitation” of sex, “which often is
enacted as an untheorized presupposition in any act of description, marks a boundary
Politics of
description
71
QRJ
14,1
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
72
that includes and excludes, that decides, as it were, what will and will not be the stuff
of the object to which we then refer” (p. 11). Like many other political philosophers,
Butler does not give credence to descriptions of things called “sex” and “gender”
without first asking how a dissenting voice regarding descriptive statements could
be accommodated. Descriptions of political situations cannot be safely mobilised
until we have agreed what it would mean to disagree, but in when having such a
discussion, the object(s) at stake must be vacated of as much substantive content as
possible. As Viviane Namaste (2009, pp. 15-17) points out in relation to Judith Butler’s
(2004) Undoing Gender, the phrases “gender politics” and “gender violence” in
relation to assaults on transgender individuals in the USA can produce exactly such
evacuations, scouring a landscape filled with class and labour relations, racialised
urban stratification, and complex interactions between sexual identity, sexual
practices and sex work, and producing instead a clean surface on which struggles
over “the human” are imagined to play out[5]. This is not an accidental failing in
Undoing Gender: Butler’s subtractions follow from her explicit commitment to
politics qua the political, which involves deferring fidelity to any single research
object. Nevertheless, this begs the question of what kinds of work subtractive
statements about political structures (here, “gender politics”) hope to perform with
regards both to their intended readers and to those about whom such texts are
written (see Namaste, 2009, p. 25). In the next section I consider this problem in
relation to familial descriptions in gender studies.
Epistemologies of the closest
Two facets of “familial” description might now be distinguished[6]. The first
involves the development of affective attachments to one’s everyday habits and
familiar persons, which in turn can be scrutinised for their broader social and political
implications (a laudable example is Caluya, 2008). The second facet is the embeddedness
of the “familiar” in the theoretical and methodological choices made by scholars
themselves, and that produce the conditions of possibility for any writing practice. If the
first “familialism” is an object of scholarship and the second an approach to scholarship,
then at key moments the two become hard to separate.
Let me give two examples, the first concise and the second more elaborate. Consider
the effect when Richard Schmitt describes his “pro-feminist” male friends in the
following way:
In our relations with women we are open to emotion: we think about our feelings and are
prepared to talk about them; we are aware of what others feel and are ready to help, support,
encourage, or cheer on. We have learned to listen and to pay careful and conscious attention
(Schmitt, 1998, p. 82).
Readers eager to practice skills learnt from critical theory may express scepticism about
Schmitt’s assessment of his own friends’ dispositions. This passage is also prescriptive
both in its intent (he implies throughout that men should be like this) and in its dialogical
aspect (one should recognise this description to be true). Nevertheless, without intentional
and dialogical prescriptions of some kind, the secondary behaviours described – help,
support, encouragement, and cheer – would be unintelligible. The problem is not simply
whether the author speaks the truth or whether the reader believes this truth, but under
what circumstances it would be possible to reflect on “help”, “support”, “encouragement”
or “cheer” without passing by way of the overdetermined political context in which such
claims tend to function (i.e. as forms of a generalisable “relation” between men and
women).
A second example of familiarity is more complicated still. In Queer Phenomenology:
Orientations, Objects, Others (2006), Sara Ahmed provides an anecdote as follows:
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
I arrive home, park my car, and walk toward the front door. A neighbour calls out to me. I look
somewhat nervously because I have yet to establish “good relations” with the neighbours.
I haven’t lived in this place very long and the semipublic of the street does not yet feel easy.
The neighbour mumbles some words, which I cannot hear, and then asks: “Is that your sister,
or your husband?” I rush into the house without offering a response. The neighbour’s utterance
is quite extraordinary. There are two women, living together, a couple of people alone in a
house. So what do you see? (Ahmed, 2006, p. 95).
The anecdote is striking in four respects developed in Ahmed’s own phenomenological
analysis. First, it repeats in a most visible way an interpellation of heterosexual
“normalcy” enacted constantly in most, though not quite all, workplaces, social
gatherings, and of course, anonymous everyday encounters. This is one version of
interpellation, a technology of “recruitment” that arranges spaces and subjects –
around gender identity, around sexual practices, around whiteness, and so on (Ahmed,
2006, p. 133). Second, this language is being used by the neighbour to “familiarise”
a stranger, not as belonging to the neighbour’s family but as conforming by analogy
to a model of proper familial belonging defined by way of exclusions (a sister living
with a brother is also excluded). As Ahmed puts it, “[this] anecdote is a reminder that
how lesbians are read often seeks to align their desire with the line of the heterosexual
couple or even the family line” (Ahmed, 2006, p. 96). The third element is that
heterosexual masculinity is here insinuated through structural implication (“if not
sisters, then husband and wife”; Ahmed, 2006, p. 96), rather than through the
attribution of stereotypical traits or behaviours. The compulsory allocation of a
“masculine” space is more forceful and less easily challenged because no particular
attributes of masculinity are named, except as the empty placeholder which “makes”
coupled women either wives or sisters.
And yet (this is feature number four) the neighbour issues no commands or
moral imperative. The injunction is already implicit in the “neighbourliness” of the
conversation itself: as Ahmed puts it in an analogous discussion, the one who is
perceived to have disrupted an assumed social consensus is “assigned to a difficult
category and a category of difficulty” (Ahmed, 2010, p. 582). Queer Phenomenology
explores aspects of such difficulties from the viewpoint of the interpellated: “we hear
the hail, and even feel its force on the surface of the skin, but we do not turn around,
even when those words are directed towards us” (Ahmed, 2006, p. 107). Pursuing these
moments when interpellation fails to actualised socially desired subject-positions
(e.g. “husband” and “wife”), Ahmed’s conclusion further develops the theme of
orientation and disorientation, noting that:
Moments of disorientation are vital[y] Disorientation as a bodily feeling can be unsettling,
and it can shatter one’s sense of confidence in the ground or one’s belief that the ground on
which we reside can support the actions that make a life feel liveable. Such a feeling of
shattering, or of being shattered, might persist and become a crisis. (Ahmed, 2006, p. 157).
There is no fixed subject for this crisis: it could happen to anyone. Ahmed is careful to
show that disorientation is not always radical, that “disorientation can be defensive
[y] [and the resulting form of politics] conservative, depending on the ‘aims’ of their
gestures” (Ahmed, 2006, p. 158). A queer politics involves not a direct transcendence of
lived spaces and situations, but a defamiliarisation of proximal spaces and objects as
one acts upon or around them. In Queer Phenomenology this means re-encountering
Politics of
description
73
QRJ
14,1
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
74
categories like “family” or “heterosexuality” as far more “strange” than we have been
led to expect (Ahmed, 2006, pp. 164-166)[7].
More has been written about disoriented reactions to interpellation than efforts to
interpellate. However, one can never be completely on this side or that of interpellative
practices: society is composed not of interpellators and interpellatees, but of collective
practices of recognition and misrecognition, hailing and being hailed. So I want to
return to our cast of unpleasant anonymous strangers – at a Melbourne station, at the
gay journalists’ conference, in the local neighbourhood – and ask: who exactly are
these people? Are they people that we have stopped being, that we must prevent others
from being, or that we are scared of becoming? I suspect not. They are more likely to
be the unknown, intolerable, overbearing and gratuitous non-relatives of moral and
political discourse. In particular, as Ahmed’s text indicates obliquely, these figures are
vital inflections of the politics of familialism. One less often sees in villainous figures
our familiars or ourselves – I could be complicit in what they are doing – and
correspondingly, we less often bear witness to the unfamiliar in friends. Practices of
recognition acquire a distinctive valency at this point. Like the present article, Queer
Phenomenology is populated by “male” and “female” characters[8]. as if they could
make sense to all readers and in the same way. My Melbournian offender was
described as a “man” but the clues I used were superficial, uncertain, and ad hoc, which
is sometimes excusable because gender recognition itself is superficial, uncertain, and
ad hoc. In some settings, this tacit appeal to the familiarities of being gendered makes
sense. But certainly not all: when we read the words “man” or “neighbour”, for
example, do we already assume by default that the person in question is “straight”
and/or “cisgendered”? Undoubtedly, the norms of heterosexuality are not policed only
by heterosexual couples, just as masculinity is not enforced only by “masculine” men
(see Ahmed, 2006, pp. 172-173). But as a reader and writer of texts, I do feel tempted
to seize upon a certain version of the gratuitous Other and to find solace in the good
selves who sit on this side of the interpellation. After all, what would a gender
“politics” be without the Other who does gender more clumsily, more crudely, or more
violently than oneself?
I am not denying the pertinence of Ahmed’s criticism of a heteronormative
interpellation that is repeated often, in a profusion of social forums, and with severe
consequences. The insidiously “neighbourly” neighbour was certainly not the first
and will not be the last. But I do want to insist that this anecdote – like, indeed,
all anecdotes – is normative. Not in the aggregative sense described by Michael
Warner in his commentary on the scientific “normalisation” of gendered sexual
practices (2000, pp. 52-61), but in the dialogic sense suggested by Morris’ criticisms of a
discourse (Mary Daly’s) that “tells you who people ‘are’, and if you know who they are
then you cannot be deceived by their discourse – including attempts to share, to join, to
make contact, or connect with your speech’ (Morris, 1988, p. 41). Such a discourse
depends on the dialogic premise that only innocents can perform the work of criticism
and that criticism is motivated by a reliable intuition for refusing interpellations and
for not interpellating others. This premise becomes most evident in the transit from
people we know to the distanced stranger who, like a well-used coat-hanger, wears the
bad deed like it fits. Queer Phenomenology is not the most obvious choice of example
to illustrate this argument, precisely because it produces an exceptionally nuanced
feeling for ambiguity and ambivalence, one lacking in much extant social scientific
research on “masculine” or “feminine” behaviours. Nevertheless, the important point
is that these textual doublings – the hero and the villain, the interpellated and the
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
interpellator, the one who turns, and the one who does not – belong to a shared social
situation, to the knots that cast “gender identification” as a difficulty at one moment
and a much needed political resource in another.
Conclusion: norms and descriptions
The concerns brought to bear on gender politics are distinct in the life experience
of the academic researcher from the mapping of nebulas or the breeding patterns of
cuttlefish. We do not criticise “gender identity” or speak in the name of “social justice” as
abstract and formal notions – we express particular outrage according to the manner by
which we are entangled, complicit, or involved. By passing through Martin Heidegger
and Simone de Beauvoir, I have tried to give greater precision to these concerns,
suggesting that “politics” (or its corollary in liberal notions like “justice”) makes
demands for gender recognition and self-identification that may preclude vital
transformations around the persistence of gender dimorphism as a dominant social
heuristic. These arguments will have been familiar to many readers, but they are worth
reiterating when considering more recent intellectual developments within queer theory,
most notably the rejection of normative classifications tout court. Lee Edelman’s (2004)
polemic against libidinal investments in social and political norms is an important recent
example; Ahmed also concurs with Tim Dean and Christopher Lane that queer theory
“advocates a politics based on resistance to all norms” (Dean and Lane, qtd. in Ahmed,
2004, p. 149), noting that “normative culture involves the differentiation between
legitimate and illegitimate ways of living whereby the preservation of what is legitimate
(‘life as we know it’) is assumed to be necessary for the well-being of the next generation”
(Ahmed, 2004, p. 149). Anti-normativity captures much of the impetus throughout the
present article: its most acute question may be characterised as, “how can we talk about
men’s relationships to gender politics without normalising some version of what it
means to be men as distinct from women?” The issues around the violence of gender
regulation raised by Wilchins, or the problems of justice and reparation explored in de
Beauvoir, could also be reframed in terms of social norms and their deviations, insofar as
the normalisation of sex/gender identities obstructs genuine political transformation.
However, I want to resist an unbounded push against norms, or the people who
subscribe to norms, as the meta-villains of political combat. In particular, it is unclear
how the Herculean effort of rejecting norms could be reconciled with an equally
important project, that of accounting for those everyday, ordinary or patterned
experiences of gendering and being gendered, from the spectacular to the banal. There
can be no appeal to ordinary repetitions without a normalisation of the vantage point
from which such regularities are observed. And no doubt, evidence produced from “pure
experience” can take “as self-evident the identities of those who experience is being
documented” and can thus “naturalise” their difference (Scott, 1991, p. 777). This, in turn,
can lead to sharp ethnocentric inflections in the dialogic production of cultural
verisimilitude (see Gilroy, 2000, p. 143). But insofar as gender scholars want to retain
some purchase on the quotidian, there must be some tolerance for the normative work of
description, or more precisely, for efforts to describe things well. Many academics
endorsing formal arguments against normativity are less eager to embrace the solipsism
that this would actually entail; more often, we want to retain some possibility of
conveying to others a recognisable or familiar impression of concrete experiences, and we
want our readers to have already been thinking in certain ways about these experiences.
From Simone de Beauvoir to Sara Ahmed, feminist philosophers have consistently
reminded their colleagues in political philosophy about the everyday character of politics
Politics of
description
75
QRJ
14,1
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
76
activated by passers-by, shop assistants, or co-workers on the floor above. These
reminders are vital because all scholars depend on familial knowledge about what is
acceptable or unacceptable, done or not done, from people that we know to those we do
not, and then again, to those we do not want to know. There is no defamiliarisation of
social identity and social norms that does not appeal to some other version of what
society might be like, according to some other plausibly everyday experience. Even
observations of “new” gender formations (“masculinities in crisis”, “post-feminist
identities”, etc.) inevitably involve re-foldings of the familiar – along new lines, perhaps,
but with well-known surfaces. Robbed of our capacity to draw tacit knowledge from
people that we know, how could we make unfamiliar situations make sense?
It may be objected that a certain existential dithering too often follows from
over-emphases on “situated” dilemmas, or that phenomenology assumes too easily
what Elspeth Probyn (1993) acutely characterised as the “self-centered self”, one that
elides the specificity of others by appealing to rhetorical modes of personal
authenticity (p. 80). In interrogating various anecdotes in a personal register, I have
tried to avoid reproducing Anthony Clare’s disingenuous claim that, despite having no
“ideology” to profess, “What I do know is what it is like to be a man” (Clare, 2001, p. 1,
emphasis in original). Speaking truthfully “as a man” cannot mean anything outside
the social provisions that make such speech possible; sometimes appeals to experience
simply provide new ways to be obnoxious and to forget oneself as a historically formed
social creature. Nevertheless, it may require just a little dithering to ask how one’s
own interpellations produce those gendered candidates for whom political heroism is
enacted, and to question the figure of the moral wrongdoer as rendered by the
omnipotent voice of the scholarly text. The question posed by performative theories of
gender is not only “how can we fight the power?”, but also, and just as importantly,
“[how] will we know the difference between the power we promote and the power we
oppose?” (Butler, 1993, p. 241).
Perhaps nobody I know is like that at a Melbourne train station. But then, my own
actions belong to “nobody I know” from the viewpoint many others. To communicate
between disparate knowledges about what “ordinary people do”, the formalisation of
political differences may be of little help – in fact, there could be such thing as too much
politics. It might be worth instead considering ways of describing, narrating, or
prescribing that do not depend on first exorcising noisy Others as the unknowable
obstacles to our own sound concerns.
Notes
1. On political ontologies see Hage (2010, pp. 115, 128).
2. On this particular reading of The Second Sex, see Butler (1986, p. 40).
3. See “The Independent Woman” and “Conclusion” in de Beauvoir (1975).
4. On gender and identification within qualitative research practices, see King (1999).
5. On the limits of Butler’s “human” see also Edelman (2004, pp. 103-105).
6. On familialism see Laurie and Stark (2012, pp. 21, 24-25).
7. On strangeness and familialism see also Ahmed (2000).
8. There are the phenomenological descriptions, in which the “woman’s body becomes the tool
in which the man ‘extends himself ’ ” (Ahmed, 2006, p. 71), or where “nausea” becomes “a
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
man losing his grip on the world” (p. 162), and there are also key players defined casually
in gendered terms: the “woman writer”, the “woman philosopher” (p. 61) and the figures
attending “same sex” desire (p. 93), among others.
References
Ahmed, S. (1998), Differences that Matter: Feminist Theory and Postmodernism, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Ahmed, S. (2000), Strange Encounters: Embodied Others in Post-Coloniality, Routledge, London.
Ahmed, S. (2004), “Queer feelings”, The Cultural Politics of Emotion, Edinburgh University
Press, Edinburgh, pp. 144-167.
Ahmed, S. (2006), Queer Phenomenology: Orientations, Objects, Others, Duke University Press,
Durham, NC.
Ahmed, S. (2010), “Killing joy: feminism and the history of happiness”, Signs, Vol. 35 No. 3,
pp. 571-594.
Althusser, L. (1971), “Ideology and ideological state apparatuses (notes towards an investigation)”,
Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, Monthly Review Press, New York, NY, pp. 127-188.
Berlant, L. (1997), The Queen of America Goes to Washington City: Essays on Sex and Citizenship,
Duke University Press, Durham, NC.
Best, S. (1999), “Driving like a boy: sexual difference, embodiment and space”, in Barcan, R. and
Buchanan, I. (Eds), Imagining Australian Space: Cultural Studies and Spatial Inquiry,
University of Western Australia Press, Nedlands, pp. 93-101.
Braidotti, R. (2011), Nomadic Subjects: Embodiment and Sexual Difference in Contemporary
Feminist Philosophy, Columbia University Press, West Sussex.
Butler, J. (1986), “Sex and gender in Simone de Beauvoir’s s second sex”, Yale French Studies,
No. 72, pp. 35-49.
Butler, J. (1993), Bodies that Matter: On the Discursive Limits of “Sex”, Routledge, New York, NY
and London.
Butler, J. (2004), Undoing Gender, Routledge, New York, NY and London.
Caluya, G. (2008), “‘The rice steamer’: race, desire and affect in Sydney’s gay scene”, Australian
Geographer, Vol. 39 No. 3, pp. 283-292.
Clare, A. (2001), On Men: Masculinity in Crisis, Arrow Books, London.
Connell, R.W. (2002), Gender, Polity, Cambridge.
de Beauvoir, S. (1948), The Ethics of Ambiguity, (Trans by Bernard Frechtman) Citadel Press,
New York, NY.
de Beauvoir, S. (1975/1949), The Second Sex, Trans., (Trans by H.M. Parshley) Penguin Books,
Middlesex.
Digby, T. (1998), “Introduction”, in Digby, T. (Ed.), Men Doing Feminism, Routledge, New York,
NY and London, pp. 1-16.
Edelman, L. (2004), “The future is kid stuff”, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, Duke
University Press, Durham, NC, pp. 1-32.
Flood, M. (2001), “Men’s collective anti-violence activism and the struggle for gender justice”,
Development, Vol. 44 No. 3, pp. 42-47.
Gall, A. (2008), “Taking/taking up: recognition and the frontier in Grenville’s The Secret River”,
Journal of the Association for the Study of Australian Literature, pp. 94-104.
Gatens, M. (2007), “The ‘disciplined imagination”, Australian Feminist Studies, Vol. 22 No. 52,
pp. 25-34.
Politics of
description
77
QRJ
14,1
Downloaded by UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE At 16:38 21 August 2014 (PT)
78
Gilroy, P. (2000), Against Race: Imagining Political Culture Beyond the Color Line, The Belknap
Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Hage, G. (2010), “The affective politics of racial mis-interpellation”, Theory Culture Society,
Vol. 27 Nos 7/8, pp. 112-129.
Hamon, P. (1982), “What is a description?”, in Todorov, T. (Ed.), French Literary Theory Today:
A Reader, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 147-178.
Heidegger, M. (2008), Being and Time, (Trans by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson) Harper
Perennial, New York, NY.
King, J.R. (1999), “Am not! Are too! Using queer standpoint in postmodern critical ethnography”,
International Journal of Qualitative Studies in Education, Vol. 12 No. 5, pp. 473-490.
Laclau, E. (2005), On Populist Reason, Verso, London and New York, NY.
Laurie, T. and Hannah, S. (2012), “Reconsidering kinship: beyond the nuclear family with Deleuze
and Guattari”, Cultural Studies Review, Vol. 18 No. 1, pp. 19-39.
Moi, T. (1990), Feminist Theory and Simone de Beauvoir, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.
Morris, M. (1988), “Amazing grace: notes on Mary Daly’s poetics”, The Pirate’s Fiancée:
Feminism, Reading, Postmodernism, Verso, London, pp. 27-50.
Morris, M. (1998), “Things to do with shopping centres”, Too Soon Too Late: History in Popular
Culture, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN, pp. 64-92.
Mouffe, C. (2013), Agonistics: Thinking the World Politically, Verso, London and New York, NY.
Namaste, V. (2009), “Undoing theory: the ‘transgender question’ and the epistemic violence of
Anglo-American feminist theory”, Hypatia, Vol. 24 No. 3, pp. 11-32.
Probyn, E. (1993), Sexing the Self: Gendered Positions in Cultural Studies, Routledge, London.
Rancière, J. (1999), Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy, (Trans by Julie Rose) University of
Minnesota, Minneapolis, MN.
Schmitt, R. (1998), “Profeminist men and their friends”, in Digby, T. (Ed.), Men Doing Feminism,
Routledge, New York, NY and London, pp. 81-98.
Scott, J.W. (1991), “The evidence of experience”, Critical Inquiry, Vol. 17 No. 4, pp. 773-797.
Warner, M. (2000), The Trouble with Normal: Sex, Politics and the Ethics of Queer Life, Harvard
University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Wilchins, R. (2002), “Queerer bodies”, in Nestle, J., Howell, C. and Wilchins, R. (Eds), Gender Queer:
Voices From Beyond the Sexual Binary, Alyson Publications, Los Angeles, CA, pp. 33-46.
Woodward, K. (2011), “The culture of boxing: sensation and affect”, Sport in History, Vol. 31 No. 4,
pp. 487-503.
Young, I.M. (1990), Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Further reading
Butler, J. (1999/1990), Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, Routledge,
New York, NY.
About the author
Dr Timothy Laurie is a Lecturer in Cultural Studies at the University of Melbourne. His
research interests include cultural studies, gender studies, philosophy, and popular music
studies. Dr Timothy Laurie can be contacted at:
[email protected]
To purchase reprints of this article please e-mail:
[email protected]
Or visit our web site for further details: www.emeraldinsight.com/reprints