CONSTANTIN PARVULESCU
THE INDIVIDUALIST
ANARCHIST DISCOURSE
OF EARLY INTERWAR GERMANY
PRESA UNIVERSITARĂ CLUJEANĂ
2018
Referenţi ştiinţifici:
Prof. univ. dr. Vasile Docea
Prof. univ. dr. Camil Ungureanu
ISBN 978‐606‐37‐0486‐4
© 2018 Autorul volumului. Toate drepturile rezervate.
Reproducerea integrală sau parţială a textului, prin orice
mijloace, fără acordul autorului, este interzisă şi se pedep‐
seşte conform legii.
Tehnoredactare computerizată: Cristian‐Marius Nuna
Universitatea Babeş‐Bolyai
Presa Universitară Clujeană
Director: Codruţa Săcelean
Str. Hasdeu nr. 51
400371 Cluj‐Napoca, România
Tel./fax: (+40)‐264‐597.401
E‐mail:
[email protected]
http://www.editura.ubbcluj.ro/
C ONTENTS
Preface .......................................................................................................... 4
Issues of Der Einzige and Key Articles ....................................................... 6
INTRODUCTION: The Century of Anarchy? .................................................. 9
CHAPTER 1: Individualist Anarchism in the Post-World War I Period ...... 26
CHAPTER 2: The Last Revolution ............................................................... 51
CHAPTER 3: Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience .................................... 77
CHAPTER 4: The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism and the Grotesque ..... 100
EPILOGUE: Individualist Anarchism in the Twenty-First Century ........... 119
Bibliography .................................................................................................. 126
3
Preface
This book is an updated version of my 2006 PhD thesis After the Revolution:
The Individualist Anarchist Journal Der Einzige and the Making of the Radical
Left in the Early Post-World War I Germany. The thesis has been available online
since its defense, and I hope that it has accompanied scholars and intellectuals
in their study of anarchism. I decided to update and publish it in book format
for two reasons. First, as I show in the Introduction, I believe that recent economic
and political developments in the EU and North America have increased the
relevance of individualist anarchist ideas. The developments that I have in mind
are the 2008 economic crisis and the subsequent Great Recession; increasing
democracy deficit in these regions; the rise of populism and of a capitalism that
prefers authoritarian state governance, as well as the resilience of religious
bigotry and xenophobia—the latter often induced from above with the help of
the state. I would also add to this list the public sphere’s increased concern with
neoliberalism and its pernicious effects on human bonding, creativity and sense
of self-fulfillment.
Each of these phenomena has revealed, in its way, the declining sovereignty
of the state in regions whose Left still believed, a decade or two ago, that the
state was the best tool to defend citizens against social and economic injustice,
wars and ecological disaster. More recently, the writings of Alain Badiou, Jacques
Rancière or Slavoj Žižek—to name just some of the center-stage figures of the
Left of this period—have all indicated, in various publications, the simulacrum
of democracy that the contemporary liberal-capitalist state offers to its citizens;
while Žižek has even overtly expressed doubt that, in the present ideological
predicament, the citizens of the Western world possess the clear judgment and
the generous drives that would make possible a functional democracy and an
acceptable quest for common good.
The second reason why I believe this book is worth publishing is because,
perhaps even more than in the days when I wrote my dissertation, the Left is
still afraid of anarchism. I offer here two reasons, which will be both addressed
by the thinkers whose work I analyze in this book. The first cause of this fear is
4
Preface
the fact that, as Noam Chomsky has emphasized in On Anarchism, the Left and its
intellectuals, are too theory bound. By that I mean, with Chomsky, that they assume
a certain role of leading intellectuals and make use of conceptual toolboxes that
the anti-authoritarian discourse of anarchism can effectively undermine.
The second reason (in part an outcome of the first) is that the Left still suspects
anarchism of any kind—and individualist anarchism in particular—to be a discourse
that can be very easily appropriated by the libertarian right—for example as
anarcho-capitalism. The Left keeps distance or criticizes anarchism because it
sees it as a trap in the service of a capitalism that has developed ideological
mechanisms to appropriate its critique and make it work for its advantage. As
such, the Left keeps distance from anarchism because it wants to make sure that
its concepts are not put into the service of neoliberal thought. This debate is not
new, and the writings I scrutinize here address it at length.
I also want to use this Preface to express my gratitude to people who believed
in my project and supported me. I would like to thank my adviser, Jack Zipes,
for his encouragement and optimism. Many thanks are also due to the members
of my dissertation committee, Rick McCormick, Eric Weitz, and the regretted
Jochen Schulte-Sasse. I am also thankful to my friends at the Bibliothek der Freien in
Berlin, to Kurt Fleming at the Stirner Archive in Leipzig, and to Hartmut Geerken,
who created the Mynona archive. A number of fellowships supported my work
on this project: a University of Minnesota Graduate Research Partnership, a
University of Minnesota Doctoral Dissertation Fellowship, a Hirschbach Fellowship,
and the year I spent in Berlin as an exchange student at Freie Universität.
5
Issues of Der Einzige and Key Articles (1919)
Date
Main Section
January 19
No. 1
Beiblatt: Der Unmensch (Der Ex Kaiser)
*
A.R., “Die letzte Revolution” Mynona, “Der gut bronzierte Floh. Eine
Rokoketterie von Mynona”
Paul Scheerbart, “Das Lachen ist verboten”
January 26
No. 2
Beiblatt: Der Unmensch
A.R., “Wo sind die Geistigen?” Mynona, “Neues Kinderspielzeug”
Panarchos, “Zu Kommunismus
und Anarchie”
February 2
No. 3
A.R., “Der Einzige bewährt
sich als Egoisten”
Beiblatt: Der Unmensch
Mynona, “Wille, Wille, Wille”
February 9
No. 4
Menshausen “Über den
völligen Bankerott jeder
staatlichen Wirtschaft
und Regierungskunst”
Beiblatt: Der Menschenfresser
Mynona, “Die vegetabilische
Vaterschaft”
February 16
No. 5
A.R., “—aber lügt nicht zu
sehr!”
Beiblatt: Das Glotzauge
February 23
No. 6
A.R., “Widersetzt Euch viel;
gehorcht wenig!”
Gerhard Lehmann,
“Apologetisches”
Beiblatt: Das (andere) Glotzauge
March 2
No. 7
Beiblatt: Die blonde Bestie
March 9
No. 8
Beiblatt: Der goetliche Sauhirt
March 16
No. 9
A. R., “Arbeit unf
Verzweiflung“
Beiblatt: Der Stockfisch
Mynona, “Der Schöpfer,” continues
through issues 10, 11, 12, 13, 14,
and 15/16
*
Literary Supplement
Anselm Ruest (1878-1943)
6
Issues of Der Einzige and Key Articles (1919)
March 23
No. 10
A.R., “Diogenes und seine
Laterne”
S. Friedlaender “Initiative”
Arthur Kahane, “Manifest
des Einzelnen”
Beiblatt: Die selbstlose Mumie
March 30
No. 11
A.R., “Und zum 4. Mal:
Revolution—ein
Schulprogram”
Beiblatt: Das ideale Gespenst
April 6
No. 12
Beiblatt: Der Familiensimpel
A.R. and SF,** “Und zum
vierten Mal: Revolution—ein
Schulprogram”
April 13
No. 13
Beiblatt: Der windschiefe Tiger
Gerhard Lehmann “An die Studenten”
(Mitteilungen der Gesellschaft für
individualistische Kultur, Stirnerbund)
April 20
No. 14
Raoul Hausmann, “Pamphlet
gegen die Weimarische
Lebensauffassung”
Beiblatt: Die Magermilchstraße
Emil Kauder, “Mitteilungen der
Gesellschaft für individualistische
Kultur (Stirnerbund)”
May 4
No. 15/16
Beiblatt: Der scrupulose Biceps
Dr. S. Friedlaender,
“Kant und die Freiheit”
Paul Gurk, “… den Tüchtigen”
Erich Barth, “Die Epidemie”
May 11
No. 17
Beiblatt: Der Philoso-Viehtreiber
May 18
No. 18
Beiblatt: Der nachträgliche Asket
Gerhard Lehmann, “Programatische
Worte” (Mitteilungen der Gesellschaft
für individualistische Kultur. Stirnerbund)
May 25
No. 19
A.R., “Die dritte Weltepoche”
Ernst Roy, “Über den
Rausch” continues through
issues 20 and 21
Beiblatt: Der Attrappist
**
Salomo Friedlaender (1871-1946)
7
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
June 1
No. 20
Beiblatt: Der falsche Hase
June 15
No. 21/22
Beiblatt: Der Beweg-Grundbesitzer
June 29
No. 23/24
Beiblatt: Der gestirnerte Himmel
Mynona, “Das Abgebrochene”
Gerhard Lehmann, “Was wir wollen”
(Mitteilungen der Gesellschaft für
individualistische Kultur. Stirnerbund)
October 15
No. 25/26
A.R., “Kopernikanische
Zeiten”
Beiblatt: Der deutsche Ichel
November 1 No. 27/28
Dr. S. Friedlaender,
“Mynona”
Beiblatt: Der Schweinerne Gast
8
INTRODUCTION
The Century of Anarchy?
In an essay tracing the influence of Herbert Marcuse‘s writings on the 1960s
German student movement, Rudi Dutschke, one of the leading figures of this
movement, reflects on the impact of the immediate post-World War I predicament
on Marcuse’s’ political views. Dutschke’s point is that the views of the author
of the One-Dimensional Man undergo an important and radical change during
this period. A bloody war had killed and wounded millions and revealed the most
beastly aspects of humankind. Death, famine, violence, and misery transformed
people and political systems. An empire, the German Kaiserreich, had fallen,
and a republic was coming into being. Revolutionary movements that were once
prohibited, exiled and persecuted, and their ideas that were once censored and
considered a danger for the common well-being could again occupy the center
space of public life. All these social, ideological and political intensities, Dutschke
argued, had an effect on thinkers of the Left. And there were many other such
intensities—some bordering on chaos, others leading to bitter disappointments.
They changed the pre-war activist Marcuse (born in 1898) into the interwar and
postwar philosopher whom we came to think of as a leading figure of the Frankfurt
School.
The year 1919 influenced Marcuse’s understanding of activism. His understanding took a turn from the political to the cultural. Active in the Workers’
and Soldiers’ Council of the Reinickendorf district of Berlin, the young Marcuse
witnessed, in Dutschke’s retelling of the story, a puzzling phenomenon of resilience
of reactionary mindsets. Newly created political structures, Marcuse observed, could
not resist ideological contamination. The social structure did not transform the
ideological superstructure; revolutionary social and political reorganization did
not create revolutionary thought. On the contrary, the unchanged superstructure
gradually managed to make revolutionary structures serve its interests.
9
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
According to Dutschke, Marcuse witnessed how the revolutionary councils
set up in the immediate postwar era very soon started to lose their political edge.
Workers and soldiers made concessions to individual interests. Small acts of
corruption emerged; but most importantly, these concessions opened the door
to practices from the past. Councils returned to electing as leaders exactly the
men whom they were supposed to expel, and who had been their bosses and
oppressors in the pre-revolutionary era. By doing so, councils lost their ability
to restructure the political-military hierarchies of the German state, and even more
the inherited forms of wielding economic power, distributing wealth and capital,
and organizing labor.1 Soon, the structures of authority of the Kaiserreich were
reinstated by the same men and women who shortly before had contested them.
Once the revolutionary ecstasy was over, the agents of change become the very
carriers of reactionary thought. Against their interest, but paying tribute to a
certain unconscious sense of order, the very workers and soldiers who carried
out the revolution became instrumental in the return of the ancien régime.
The cultural shift in Marcuse’s thinking was the effect of this experience.
One can speculate that this experience affected the entire intellectual movement
that we call the Frankfurt School. Moreover, one should remember that it is Rudi
Dutschke recounting the story, who had his share of disappointment with the
1968 movement. In this line, one can go one step further and speak about a
format of storytelling, characterized by a post-revolutionary state of mind. It is
a standpoint of defeat, of being in the aftermath of something (wars and failed
revolutions)—that is, of being “post.” This standpoint also brings the concepts of
poststructuralism closer to those of individualist anarchism—the latter developing
in the skeptical atmosphere that follows the acknowledgement of the defeat of
communism by Stalinism in Western Europe, especially France, and the defeat
of the ‘68 movements by the capitalist corporate state.
I will refer here only to the “post” experience of the Left and to the red line
in its history that this storytelling format generates from 1918 through 1956,
1
“Während der ersten Monate nach dem Kriegabschluss von 1918 [Marcuse] erlebte, wie Offiziere,
statt davongejagen zu werden, zu Delegierten genannt wurden, wie die deutschen Räte der
unmittelbaren Selbstverwaltung für den Augenblick auftauchten und gesellschaftlich fast spurlos
verschwanden. Weder wurden die Paläste enteignet noch die militärische Führung und das preußische
Kastensystem gesprengt, ganz zu schweigen vom Rüstungskapital, Bankensystem usw.” Rudi
Dutschke, Die Revolte, 138.
10
Introduction
1968, 1989, and the post-2008 Great Recession era.2 This post-revolutionary
gaze is concerned with yet another aspect of the revolution—a certain practical
spirit and cynicism that characterizes revolutionary contexts, and which splits
revolutionary agency between a leading avant-garde and a manipulable and
executing mass. Marcuse’s revelation that the revolution did not happen in the
minds of the Germans and that the battalions of workers were not trusted to be
able to define and follow their interest without transcendent guidance was no
secret for leaders of the Left such as Rosa Luxemburg and V.I. Lenin. After
going through their own disappointments, they tailored their political theory
and praxis in this dualist fashion, that was qualified as cynical within the postrevolutionary narrative.3
Emphasis on the cynicism of revolutionary leaders would generate the trope
of the stolen or betrayed revolution, which will also become a mantra of the
soliloquies of the post-1989 Left or of Great Recession radicalism as practiced
for example in Greece and Spain.4 For Marcuse, the experience of 1918-1919
marked a departure from a nineteenth-century understanding of revolution, whose
most prominent manifestation was the Soviet Revolution started a year earlier
in Moscow. He realized that power functioned in a more complex way than its
manifestation in and reproduction through political institutions. Based on this
new way of understanding power, 1918 and 1919 became landmark years for
him and for many others who lived through these times. These years allowed the
development of a new (twentieth-century) understanding of political militancy,
and whose most prominent outbreak in the Northern hemisphere would occur in
1968. The questions that troubled the young Marcuse—the revolution in “the
minds and souls of people” and the legitimacy of party elites—would haunt
revolutionary movements throughout the twentieth century. They laid the groundwork for the birth of the New Left, which was itself incapable of answering
these questions and just generated new dilemmas. After the anti-climactic endings
of the anti-globalization and occupy movements, and the sliding into Islamism
of the Arab liberation movements, the questions of 1919 still haunt the Left. The
2
3
4
Left-Wing Melancholia: Marxism, History, and Memory. New York: Columbia University
Press, 2017.
Rudi Dutschke, Die Revolte, 141.
Siani-Davies, The Romanian Revolution of 1989. 277; Cas Mudde and Cristobal Rovira
Kaltwasse Populism: A Very Short Introduction, 37.
11
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
proof of their importance is perhaps best illustrated by the writings of thinkers
such as Mark Fisher, Wolfgang Streeck and Slavoj Žižek, who, among many
others, publicly acknowledged that there is no revolutionary movement of the
Left that can place itself outside the current order, and that the current order of
late-capitalism is expected to implode, without any clear representation of what
would come next.5
*
This book revisits the early days of the cultural turn and of the New Left
with the purpose of shedding fresh light on them, and of entering a dialogue
with these early days of the New Left that would make them address the present
terminal condition of capitalism. In the spirit of Dutschke’s exploration of this
period, my project returns to this site in order to trace some of the questions that
tormented the twentieth century. This dialogue is carried out with a movement that,
in 1919, insistently asked these questions. This movement was the individualist
anarchism of the journal Der Einzige. My study aims to recover the answers
given by an unusual group of leftist mavericks who edited and published in this
journal, and to show their possible ties to the twentieth and twenty-first century
radical democratic movements.
This revisitation is motivated by another goal: I intend to focus not only on
the concerns that link Der Einzige with the contemporary Left, but also on
important differences. In spite of the fact that many ideas and practices of the
immediate post-World War I period were inspirational to twentieth-century
political activism, there was also a remainder, a rich and relevant political
thought that was marginalized. 1918-1919 represented an unparalleled intellectual
outbreak. It marked an opening in history—a moment in which radical change
seemed possible. But not all the insights that this privileged period brought to
light entered the canon of progressive thought. Der Einzige’s individualist
anarchism was one of these insightful contributions to radical thought that the
Left unjustly chose to exclude. Its effect on the twentieth century is thus that of
a lack, of a necessary but missing complementary discourse.
5
Wolfgang Streeck, How Will Capitalism End?; Slavoj Žižek, Living in the Endtimes; Mark Fisher
Capitalist Realism: Is There no Alternative?
12
Introduction
The framework and the concepts of twentieth-century political thought (alienation vs. liberation, civilization vs. barbarism, democracy vs. tyranny, freedom
of speech vs. censorship, human rights vs. totalitarianism, etc.) and the realities
that informed them (the world wars, colonization and decolonization, economic
crises, globalization, and neoliberalism) could not allow a complete grasp of
individualist anarchism’s intellectual potential. Dutschke recalls that, in spite of
their call to direct action, their pacifism, their respect for diversity, and their antiauthoritarian stance, most of the 1968 movements failed to be radical enough when
it came to rebuilding the internal structures of the movement and to rethink the
discourse on the subject and individual agency. I referred to Dutschke extensively
in these opening paragraphs because Der Einzige’s anarchism had articulated
responses to his dilemmas and anticipated both the cultural turn and the rethinking
of individual and collective agency.
Der Einzige’s anarchism, I will show, also provided an insightful but mostly
ignored critique of humanist discourse and of the concept of human (Mensch).
It challenged historical necessity and proposed an original framework for understanding social change in which individual revolt played a central role. Some of these
ideas reappeared—rarely acknowledging their individualist anarchist heritage—
in writings produced in the aftermath of the ‘68 movement, within post-structuralist
theory. They can be traced to concepts developed by its French proponents, Michel
Foucault, Gilles Deleuze, Félix Guattari, Jean-Luc Nancy, Jacques Rancière, and
Jacques Derrida, though these thinkers hardly wrote on individualist anarchism,
and most of them would probably identify themselves as Marxists or socialists.6
Yet the return of individualist anarchist ideas in poststructuralist concepts
and in the concepts that emerged from the debates of the 1980s and 1990s was
instrumental in leading the Left into the twenty-first century, and helped provide
a different rhetoric to address the neoliberal condition. According to some of
the early twenty-first century Left’s most notable promoters, Antonio Negri and
Michael Hardt, one of the key features of this “new” New Left is its understanding
6
In Specters of Marx, Jacques Derrida addresses Stirner’s work at length. Deleuze has discussed
Stirner briefly but admiringly in Nietzsche and Philosophy (1962). Although Derrida does not
state it directly, one can notice a cautious consideration of Stirner as an alternative to Marx.
The “New International” advocated by Derrida in this book, which is written as a reflection on
the fall of East European communism, is an effort to rethink the Left for the twenty-first century.
13
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
of sovereignty.7 Following Hardt and Negri, I argue that the twentieth-century
Left, in the name of which Dutschke spoke, could not overcome the opposition
“sovereignty vs. anarchy” (anarchy understood here pejoratively) because it
employed an ineffective approach to sovereignty. It was ineffective because it
could not develop outside a statist framework, and consequently it was unable
to process decentered forms of sovereignty in the globalized world order and
develop concepts that could design effective cultural and political action to
democratize the global predicament, which Der Einzige’s anarchism had already
outlined.
*
Although my project focuses on the interwar years of the German individualist anarchist movement, I also take into account its earlier days, starting
with its pioneer text, Max Stirner’s Der Einzige und sein Eigentum (1845) and
the birth of individualist anarchism as an intellectual and political movement
forty-six years later with the publication of John Henry Mackay’s influential
The Anarchists (Die Anarchisten) (1891). In the post-World War I period, individualist anarchism was short lived. In a century that was statist in political
thinking, and in which political and economic agents followed the imperative of
concentrating the power of organizations and increasing the effectiveness of
their interventions; individualist anarchism’s insights found few adherents. By the
early 1920s, this movement disappeared, and its revivals would be ephemeral.
During the early interwar years, individualist anarchism reached its point of
maximum intellectual sophistication. One locus of such high intellectual complexity
was the weekly Der Einzige, which appeared in 1919 and was edited by two
original German thinkers, Anselm Ruest (Ernst Salomon) and Salomo Friedlaender/
Mynona.8 Because of the unpopularity of individualist anarchist ideas in the
twentieth century there are few books that have examined it, and even fewer have
grasped its intellectual richness. Little has been written on Der Einzige. So far,
the journal has been discussed by two authors, only briefly and only historically,
7
8
See Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Multitude, 329.
Pre-World War I individualist anarchism had two languages, German and English. It was in
Germany and in the US that individualist anarchism flourished: in the works of authors such as
Max Stirner, John Henry Mackay and Anselm Ruest in Germany, and Josiah Warren, Benjamin
Tucker, Dora Marsden, and, to a certain extent, Emma Goldman in the US.
14
Introduction
and not for the sake of uncovering its relevance within the individualist anarchist
movement. In Left-Wing Nietzscheans, Seth Taylor reads Der Einzige, as the title
of his book suggests, as part of an effort to reveal the way Nietzsche’s concepts
fertilized those of the Left. Mainly a Striner scholar, Taylor develops ideas similar
to those articulated by Der Einzige around the concept of postanarchism.9 Though
Dieter Lehner’s Individualanarchismus und Dadaismus (Individualist anarchism
and Dadaism) is thoroughly documented, it is not concerned with drawing a
profile of the publication. To a certain extent, the book does aim to emphasize
the post-World War I transformations of individualist anarchism, but Lehner’s
major concern is to highlight the way in which Anselm Ruest and Friedlaender/
Mynona provided the Dada movement with philosophical and literary models.
Nor is there any study that deals with the work of Anselm Ruest. Dirk
Heißerer’s Verschwinden und Erinnern: auf den Spuren von Anselm Ruest und
Salomo Friedlaender/ Mynona (Disappearance and Remembering: Following
the Footsteps of Anselm Ruest and Salomo Friedlaender/ Mynona) provides a
knowledgeable overview of the life and work of the two thinkers, but it focuses
primarily on their literary output and on their years of exile, and less on their
individualist anarchist ideas. Literary and philosophical scholarship have produced
a few books on Friedlaender/ Mynona, but none of these explores the individualist
anarchist dimension of his work, and his activity as editor of Der Einzige is
neglected. An editorial effort worth mentioning is the reprint of the journal by
Hartmut Geerken.10 Geerken has also rescued Ruest and Friedlaender/ Mynona’s
unpublished philosophical manuscripts and has reprinted part of them. Friedlaender/
Mynona’s autobiography Ich (I), his philosophical opus Das magische Ich
(The Magical I), and Anselm Ruest’s Zum wirklichen Ich: Prolegomena zum
Personalismus (Towards the True I: Prolegomena to Personalism) have been saved
from obliteration and have seen the light of print due to the efforts of this dedicated
intellectual.
My study draws on the work of a series of authors who have produced
“genealogical” studies that aim at bringing to the fore the anarchist roots of
poststructuralist theory. Todd May and Saul Newman are the household names
here. My study, however, does not concentrate on filiations. It is not an effort to
9
10
Saul Newman. The Politics of Postanarchism.
Hartmut Geerken (Ed.), Der Einzige, Munich, Kraus Reprint, 1985.
15
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
highlight the way in which one group of thinkers has anticipated another more
than half a century later, in spite of the fact that these thinkers were riddled by
similar dilemmas regarding humanism, the transparency of language, truth, binary
thinking, the functioning of power, universalism, revolution, representation, class,
intersubjectivity, the metaphysics of presence (see individualist anarchism’s
Goethean motto: “Ich hab’ mein Sach’ auf Nichts gestellt” [I’ve set my thing on
no-thing]), singularity, and affirmation.11 There are, however, also major differences
between these positions, as for example Félix Guattari’s rejection of individual
revolt, a central practice within individualist anarchism’s understanding of political
action.12 My argument is that the emergence of poststructuralism signals a time
that is more receptive to individualist anarchist ideas, and that poststructuralist
concepts help one render insightful the act of remembering performed in this book.
*
Philosophical anarchism, like postcolonial or feminist theory, is an exercise
in thinking beyond hegemonic naturalized intellectual structures, structures that
inform language, everyday practices, institutions, and political imagination.
Philosophical anarchism’s challenge to think beyond given structures refers to
envisioning the political outside statist and organized frameworks. In 1919, within
this framework, Der Einzige asked a series of fundamental questions regarding
the ends of man and politics. In the aftermath of the bloodbath of World War I,
and after the crumbling of the oppressive corporate German imperial state, Der
Einzige asked: why rulers, why state again? Why authority, allegiance to collective
causes, obedience, order, grand values, collective beliefs, socially defined vocations,
and social organization that is not spontaneous? The list is of course longer; in
fact infinite, since anarchists stand for the radical questioning of anything imposed
or ideologically given.
Appearing at a time that was, as Derrida puts it, “out of joint,” Der Einzige’s
political intervention aimed at preventing the arrest of history within yet another
grand political project. Out of joint refers here to the potential of the in-between—
11
12
This is the motto of Stirner’s Der Einzige und sein Eigentum. Contemporary trends in anarchism,
such as postanarchism and postsocialist anarchism, espouse poststructuralist and individualist
anarchist concepts.
See Félix Guattari, Chaosophy, 60.
16
Introduction
situated on the boundary of the not yet and the no longer.13 It aimed at keeping
history open by spreading a culture of disobedience and permanent revolt. For
Der Einzige, undoing the idea of the human was the main strategy of preserving
the openness of history. The experience of the nineteenth-century state that
culminated in World War I revealed, as Jacques Derrida puts it at the end of the
twentieth century, that “man, a certain determined concept of man, is finished,
[and that] the true humanity of man, of the other man of man as other begins or
has finally the chance of heralding itself—of promising itself in an apparently
inhuman or else a-human fashion.”14
In 1919, Der Einzige sent the twentieth-century Left an invitation to live
dangerously: to keep the future of communities open, abandon humanism, rethink
the aims and tactics of political action, and overcome the statist horizon of
understanding and managing the commons. It called upon the Left to think power
differently, not to organize in order to create sovereign bodies and group antagonisms that lead to wars, but to leave everybody’s future in his or her own hands.
It called on individuals not to immerse into a mass, not to accept being treated
as such, but to struggle to discover their own self-interest, emancipate via the
assertion of this interest, and free their minds of the burdening duty of being
human. In one word, they called for revolt—a generalized revolt fought on all
fronts, from class to gender, as well as from work to family relations.
Der Einzige’s intervention was, however, theoretical and radical, that is,
willingly un-realistic and not a doctrine or the groundwork of a policy. This is
why a “realist” approach to the writings of individualist anarchists proves fruitless.
Der Einzige refused to think within the margins of the spectacle of the possible,
within the leeway that was bestowed by (hegemonic) ideology on political
imagination. Its radicalism was neither practice-oriented nor descriptive. It was
abusive; its role was to disrupt and not to explain, suggest or enforce.
The main target of individual revolt was the human (der Mensch). Discourse
on who the human or the individual is constituted, in their view, the original
falsification of politics, the myth of myths upon which a pernicious understanding
of community was built. The human was the essence that founded a politics that
suffered from horror vacui, a politics of presence, organization and mobilization.
13
14
Jacques Derrida, Specters of Marx, 12.
Jacques Derrida, Specters of Marx, 73.
17
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
Individualist anarchists called their revolt against “man” egotism. It meant both
rejection of the political construction “man” (the new God of the secular society),
and the affirmation of something that existed, as absence, founded on nothing,
the Ich, the I as singularity.
Der Einzige was written not only with an eye on the “hijacked” 1918-1919
German popular revolt, but also on the 1917 Soviet revolution that turned into a
repressive regime and the German grand mobilization of August 1914 that generated
the World War I bloodbath. Like the post-cultural turn of Marcuse (but years before
him), Der Einzige believed that change could not be awaited from organized
masses, led by an avant-garde. Nor there was any script of a revolution, derived
from a political platform. In Der Einzige’s vision, collective revolts needed to
emerge, spread and generate impact differently. The best metaphor to describe
them and the way in which individualist anarchists understood the shift from
the singular to the multiple was that of a viral epidemic. Change would spread
gradually, Der Einzige argued, from one individual to another:
The new era is not born in one day, but the doctrines of egoism, will hopefully
convince more and more individuals that their interest lies beyond the “social
interest” until they are strong enough to prevail.15
This gradual infestation with the ideas of individualist anarchism is, however,
not reform; and also not a prologue to Dutschke’s Gramscian post-1968 project
of the long march through the institutions. First, because an epidemic spreads in
an uncontrolled fashion; second, individual revolt does not have a “platform,” but
is pure rebellion; third, because infection always presupposes a possible mutation,
which means that there is no ideological continuity in the act of political change.
And fourth, because it does not rely on a representative or sovereign body, but
on dispersed strategies of territorialization. One does not know how, why or even
where exactly a disease starts; its moments of intensity and relapse are hard to
foresee. Science knows that epidemics readily contaminate susceptible bodies:
the weak, the sickened, and the marginal, but preventive interventions by the
apparatuses in charge of containing them—immunization and isolation—are
very often inefficient if they do not constrain the entire population.
15
“Die neue Ära wird nicht an einem Tage geboren, sondern die Lehren des Egoismus überzeugen,
wenn es ihnen gelingt, immer mehr Einzelne, dass ihre Interesse jeneseits des “Gesellschaftsinteresses” liegt, bis sie stark genug sind, sich durchzusetzen.” Benedict Lachmann, Protagoras,
Nietzsche, Stirner, 65.
18
Introduction
The metaphor of a viral epidemic explains individual rebellion not only through
its disorganized sprawl, but also through the active participation of each contaminated
body in the perpetuation of the disease. Viruses lack identity, and they are not true
living beings, that is, they cannot multiply by themselves. The infected body is
not the passive object of a disease. It is a producer and an agent of the mutation
of the virus. An infected collectivity is not a mass. Each body breeds and transforms
the virus to resist countermeasures and spreads it by its own means.
Individual rebellion both sickens and makes the body susceptible to subsequent
contagious diseases. It transforms the vigorous and well-organized community
administered by state apparatuses into a susceptible entity. It renders the health
of the multitude unstable by undermining the structures of immunity that have
been cast upon it. For Der Einzige, this epidemic was an illness with an infinity of
symptoms and one effect: the unexpected implosion of the structures of authority.16
The germ of disobedience would render superfluous laws, social rituals and the
mythology of organization. The singularity would overcome its induced existential
incompleteness and step up to a face-to-face encounter with the other, a situation
no longer mediated by codes of conduct.
*
Individualist anarchists often used the term Egoismus to mark the idea of
individual revolt. Egoismus, as Max Stirner understood it, referred to a revolt
against abstractions and universals. Egoismus stood for placing one’s “Sach’”
on nothing. It pointed to a personal imperative—“follow only your interest”—
which rested on the absence of a definition of being human. More than a practice
Egoismus was, like the Cartesian cogito, a hypothesis upon which the singularity
could produce its autonomy. Stirner referred to the subject of this revolt as the
Ich—which he capitalized.17 He also called it Einzige and opposed it to the
Einzelne, who was the individual as understood by nineteenth-century liberalism.
The Einzelne was the one in the crowd, the one individual version of a shared
essence (man/ human). It was countable, comparable and self-identical in time,
while the Einzige was in a singular relationship to the other and to itself, and
preserved no fixed continuity of self in time.
16
17
A similar eschatology is offered by Streeck for the end of capitalism.
He and later Der Einzige capitalized personal pronouns in order to highlight singularity.
19
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
The standard English translation of Stirner’s opus Der Einzige und sein
Eigentum is The Ego and Its Own and goes back to 1907 to Steven T. Byington’s
rendering edited by Benjamin Tucker. I believe this edition is dated, and the
concepts I employ in this book suggest that The Singularity and Its Sovereignty
would be a better translation.18 It would make individualist anarchist thought
more relevant for the twenty-first century. Thus the translation of the title of the
journal I focus on: Der Einzige: The Singularity.
I also do not translate the German “Egoismus” with the English “egoism” as
has been done in most texts by or on Stirner.19 My preference is for “egotism.”20
Both translation choices, “singularity” and “egotism,” aim at distancing individualist
anarchism from liberal individualism, right-wing libertarianism, and the idealism
of the ego. “Egoism” has often been used with reference to the idealist philosophy of thinkers such as George Berkeley and Christian Wolff. It also connotes
solipsism and thus obscures the social dimension of individualist anarchist rebellion.
“Egotism” refers instead to concrete existential choices and distances individualist
anarchism from idealism. Moreover, because in common English it bears negative
connotations, it better expresses the rebellious nature of Stirner’s “individualism,”
which, in contrast to liberal and neo-liberal individualism, is not a tool for a subtler
integration of the singularity within the organized community (as imagined by
thinkers such as John Stuart Mill), but an agent of its destabilization.
18
19
20
In fact, Byington admits that his choice of words is imperfect. In the “Translator’s Introduction,”
he argues that other versions would have been even more imperfect. This again can be seen as
a symptom of the failure of the twentieth century to understand Stirner. For Byington, the
impossibility of finding a better translation lies in language itself. Byington’s tribulations
don’t seem, however, to grasp the problem, which is not stylistic, but epistemological. Finding
the English equivalent becomes tantamount to a breakthrough in political philosophy:
“The Ego and His Own” is not an exact English equivalent of “Der Einzige und sein Eigentum.”
But then, there is no exact English equivalent. Perhaps the nearest is “The Unique One and
His Property.” But the unique one is not strictly the Einzige, for uniqueness connotes not
only singleness but an admirable singleness, while Stirner's Einzigkeit is admirable in his
eyes only as such, it being no part of the purpose of his book to distinguish a particular
Einzigkeit as more excellent than another. Moreover, “The Unique One and His Property”
has no graces to compel our forgiveness of its slight inaccuracy. It is clumsy and unattractive.
And the same objections may be urged with still greater force against all the other renderings
that have been suggested,—“The Single One and His Property,” “The Only One and His
Property,” “The Lone One and His Property,” “The Unit and His Property,” and, last and least
and worst, “The Individual and His Prerogative” (ix-x).
For R.W.K. Paterson’s canonic study (The Nihilistic Egoist: Max Stirner. London: Oxford
University Press, 1971), Stirner is the philosopher of egoism.
German does not have these two variants, egoism and egotism. Egoismus indicates both.
20
Introduction
In the case of right-wing libertarianism, such tools of integration would be
accumulation of capital (economic property) or the free market—which neither
Stirner nor Der Einzige endorsed.21 As I will show later, the generalized rebellion
proposed by Der Einzige imagined the thinker as a person without belief in a
social religion. For anarchists, capitalism and its main forms of organization
required such religious behavior. Both Stirner and his anarchist followers were
quick to reveal the oppression that capitalist piety and the free market generated.
First, they emphasized that the free market was not self-regulating, and that, as
a product of the state, it reinforced the role of its creator as economic arbiter and
intervener in times of crisis. Second, they argued that the free market generated
economic oppression, which led to political oppression, contradicting the very
basic principles of anarchism. Third, and most importantly, they showed that
the window of freedom that the free market offered was in fact very narrow,
restricted to capitalist relations of production and competition—the latter creating
unfavorable conditions for developing one’s ownness and singularity in the
spirit of individualist anarchism.22
The choice for the term singularity on behalf of “individual,” “ego,” “the
one,” or “the unique,” follows the same line of thought. It brings to the fore the
temporary, concrete, and indefinable aspect of Stirner’s Ich. The choice for
“singularity” also expresses my intention to differentiate individualist anarchist
discourse from right-wing libertarianism, whose radical individualist heroes
(descending from Randian literature) are clearly outlined racially (white heterosexual), morally (resolution, discipline, hard work) and politically (in a capitalist
context).23 I also use singularity in order to link individualist anarchism with
concepts of poststructuralist thinkers, for whom, as Gilles Deleuze’s Pure
Immanence and Jean-Luc Nancy’s The Inoperative Community highlight,
“singularity” is used as a beacon of an anti-essentialist and antihumanist
approach to the political.24
21
22
23
24
Saul Newman, Max Stirner, 181.
Saul Newman, The Politics of Postanarchism, 28, 43.
For example as appearing in Ayn Rand’s Atlas Shrugged.
In Pure Immanence, Deleuze proposes an alternative to traditional humanist discourse by
interpellating the Ich not as individual, but as singularity. He proposes a “metaphysics” of
virtuality in which the mark of the singularity is the fact that it is living the indeterminate life,
a life. The singular life is a life, as opposed to the individual life which is the life, the
determined life (30).
21
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
I should also mention that I use the term individualist anarchism to make
reference to a movement that was essentially non-essentialist. I see it as an
assemblage of discourses reflecting on the singularity of the subject and its
historical landmarks and a development scenario in a fight for indetermination. As
such, individualist anarchism qualifies a movement within which Der Einzige
was a voice—though its editors rejected the label. John Henry Mackay coined
the term “individualist anarchism” in an effort to distance his Stirner-inspired
anarchism from communist and revolutionary anarchism. It is possible that the
contributors to Der Einzige refused this label because they did not want to be
associated with Mackay’s circle. In 1919, Friedlaender/ Mynona called himself
a polarist, and Ruest thought of himself as a radical individualist. The discussion
group around Der Einzige was called the Society for Individualistic Culture, and
later, in 1920, Ruest founded an Individualistenbund. Individualism, however,
was also problematic and could inspire unwanted misinterpretations: liberalism
and Nietzsche-inspired aristocratism. Many leftist followers of Stirner and Nietzsche
avoided using it, and this might be the reason why later Ruest referred to his
Stirner-inspired philosophy as “personalism.”
I argue that it is critical for my project to work with the term “individualist
anarchism” because it reveals the continuity of an intellectual effort, which, even
if it underwent several metamorphoses, has preserved the original Stirnerian
impetus. It also stresses the multiple connections of Der Einzige with the radical
Left. If, according to Daniel Guerin, “anarchism” stands for a movement whose
main characteristics are revolt (instead of organized revolutions), anti-statism,
rejection of representative democracy (and of its marriage with capitalism) and
authoritarian socialism (with its party elites and its scientific methods), promotion
of alternative forms of organization, and rethinking of bourgeois morality;25
individualist anarchism is a radicalization of these features. Anarchism developed
from a critique of both the socialist Left and the capitalist and fascist Right,
and looked for a “third way” of doing politics that would not be based on the
principle of authority (arche, ergo an-arche-ism), which it saw as the main cause
of human alienation. Individualist anarchism brought this critique of the organized
community to its perhaps ultimate consequence: antihumanism.
25
Daniel Guerin, Anarchism, 13-43.
22
Introduction
Similar designators for individualist anarchism could be “Stirnerian anarchism”
or “antihumanist anarchism.” In all cases, their radicalism originates in the fact
that they trace authority at the biopolitical level of subject production and reject
any forms of organization (anarchist federalism), class struggle (communist
anarchism), the idea of revolution and a revolutionary elite (as envisioned by
Kropotkinist anarchists), and the rule of the free market (anarcho-capitalists).
Individualist anarchism promotes individual revolt and envisages the spread of
this revolt more like an epidemic than like an organized assault of the Winter
Palace. If relevant change should happen, it would not be in the form of political
organization via a revolution, or via intensified exchanges on liberated global
markets. For individualist anarchists, change is first and foremost cultural and is
contingent upon individual liberation, that is, liberation not only at the level of
each individual but with the means of each individual. This is why individualist
anarchists used the word state to refer not only to the traditional institutions that
grant monopoly of power, but also to structures of cognitive mapping and knowledge. “State” becomes a metaphor for everything that works for the organization
of a community: virtues, beliefs, values, signs, and markets.
*
All these ideas result from the Stirner impetus and his “relentless critique of
piety and bold hopes for ownness [individual sovereignty].”26 The journal Der
Einzige was one expression of this impetus. Other revivals occurred during the
“roaring sixties” of Dutschke and continued in various forms and in various
locations around the world queering and barbarizing new forms of power and
order specific to the era of globalization.27 The fact that the only visual document
we have of Stirner is a caricature drawn from memory by Engels is a good metaphor
to explain the silences and the distortions of Stirner’s legacy. A relevant inventory
of these distortions, as well as an intelligent rejection of them, can be found in
Saul Newman’s Max Stirner. I will refer here only to a few that are relevant to
the year 1919—mainly Stirner’s defamation in socialist literature.
Most twentieth-century accounts of him were, like Engels’ depiction, signed
by hostile authors (very often hardline Marxists), and with the explicit goal of
26
27
Saul Newman, Max Stirner, 183.
The concept of generalized revolt and of its agency, the barbarian (as opposed to the Randian
hero), can be found in Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire.
23
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
consigning his work to the trash can of history. The book that set the tone for the
critique of individualist anarchism was Marx and Engels’s The German Ideology,
mainly an aggressive, unfair, and, I would argue along with many Stirner scholars,
desperate anti-Stirner pamphlet.28 It regarded Stirner’s thinking as petit bourgeois
(and ivory-tower) and as a breeding ground for reactionary discourse. Inspired by
Marx and Engels, twentieth-century Stirner critics focused on the “adventurous”
nature of his idea of revolt,29 and on the complicity of Stirner-inspired thinking
with fascism30 and global capitalism.31
Like that of a Dostoevskian hero, Stirner’s biography is veiled in mystery.
Max Stirner was a pseudonym for Johann Caspar Schmidt (1806-1856). He studied
philosophy, worked as a teacher and journalist, and became a central figure of
the Berlin bohemia at the Hippel, where he mingled with the “Berliner Freien”
(Young Hegelians). He wrote only one philosophical opus, Der Einzige und sein
Eigentum, published in Leipzig by Otto Wiegand in 1845, and well received in
the immediate period after its publication, especially among the youth. However,
it was also very quickly forgotten on the eve of 1848, when the radical circles
thought of revolution and armed rebellions. Because of its radical anti-Church
and anti-state stance, the book was immediately censored, like almost every
project signed by Stirner’s radical Hippel companions. Nevertheless, it was allowed
back into bookstores after a few days. The reason was that the ideas of Der
Einzige und sein Eigentum seemed to the censors too absurd to pose any danger
to the social order. The authorities proved to be right in their intuition. In the
post 1848 era, Stirner was totally forgotten.32
Nietzsche was the other inspiring figure for Der Einzige. There is a long and
unsolved debate whether Nietzsche had read Stirner or not, a debate which was
28
29
30
31
32
Desperate because Stirner’s radical take on organization and his anti-humanism posed
uncomfortable questions to the naïve humanism of the early Marx and his organizational
practices. According to Bernd Laska (“Dissident geblieben”), the discourse of historical
materialism developed in The German Ideology is crafted to become a philosophy immune to
Stirner’s criticism. For Paul Thomas, Stirner awakened the Hegel in Marx (34).
See, for example, Heinz Holz in Die abenteuerliche Rebellion.
See Hans Helms Die Ideologie der anonymen Gesellschaft: Max Stirners “Einziger” und der
Fortschritt des demokratischen Selbstbewußtseins vom Vormärz bis zur Bundesrepublik.
See, for example, Murray Bookchin, Social Anarchism and Lifestyle Anarchism: The Unbridgeable
Chasm. His argument—a common one within the organized Left—is that individualist anarchism
cannot oppose capitalism because it does not accept macro-theories of emancipation and has
no clear vision of the final reconciliation of antagonizing political forces.
John Henry Mackay, Max Stirner, 127-131.
24
Introduction
also hosted by Der Einzige, but which I will not detail here. There are, however,
two main points emerging from this debate that need to be emphasized: first
that, regardless of whether Nietzsche had or had not read Stirner, he developed
some of Stirner’s ideas and Der Einzige integrated this “development,” which
in turn individualized its voice within the individualist anarchist movement.
Second, what was called the “Stirner Renaissance” of the 1890s is impossible
to imagine without the surging interest in Nietzsche, which also started making
headway in the socialist movement of the 1890s.33 Stirner inspired Der Einzige’s
critique of the organized world. Nietzsche offered Der Einzige an “attitude,” a
“style,” an existential experience of writing that expressed passion for the sublime
of the super-human.34 For Der Einzige, this form of writing exemplified revolt
itself and completed Stirner’s critical insights against piety with an emphasis on
rebellious and non-dialectical affirmation.
*
This book discusses Der Einzige’s ideas in four chapters. Chapter 1 provides
historical information about the journal and biographical and intellectual profiles
of its contributors; it looks at the immediate postwar context in which the journal
appeared and locates Der Einzige’s significance within the Stirner Renaissance
and its roots in the 1890 split of the Left and the turn-of-the-century bohemia.
Chapter 2 focuses on Der Einzige’s critique of the organized community, revolutionary
practices and the idea of mobilization, and brings to the fore the journal’s vision
of communal living centered on antihumanism, singularity and individual revolt.
Chapter 3 studies Der Einzige’s understanding of language, concepts and the
production of meaning; the journal’s role as a medium of mass-communication
and that of its editors as intellectuals; its invitation to disobedient reading, creation
and active forgetting. Chapter 4 highlights the dialogue between the main section
of the journal and its literary supplement, focuses on Friedlaender/ Mynona’s
contributions, his philosophical ideas, and emphasizes the individualist anarchist
roots of the literary genre of the grotesque. Finally, an Epilogue looks at recent
variations on the individualist anarchist theme.
33
34
See Steven Aschheim, The Nietzsche Legacy in Germany, 168. Some of the early leftist
Nietzscheans are Gustav Landauer and Bruno Wille. They also rediscover Stirner.
Friedrich, Nietzsche. Ecce Homo, 51.
25
CHAPTER 1
Individualist Anarchism
in the Post-World War I Period
Mushrooms Shooting Out of the Ground
An entry in the diaries of Count Harry Kessler, dated Wednesday, February 19,
1919 reads:
I received a letter from Anselm Ruest asking indirectly for financial assistance
for his magazine. Publications, some interesting in part, are shooting out of the
ground like mushrooms.35
Kessler was a Weimar era celebrity. A dandy diplomat, patron of the arts, and
publisher, he kept a 10,000-page diary of the tumultuous times of German
change from decline of the Kaiserreich, through World War I, the world economic
crisis, to the rise to power of Nazism. The quoted entry refers to a name, a
journal, a problem, and an era. The name was in fact a pen name. Anselm Ruest
stood for Ernst Salomon, and was a well-known figure of the radical and
expressionist press. He was co-founder of the journals Die Aktion and Bücherei
Maiandros; book and magazine editor, notorious individualist anarchist, and author
of a Max Stirner study and a Max Stirner compilation. The journal was Der Einzige,
which Ruest started together with an even better-known figure of the turn of
the century radical scene, Salomo Friedlaender/ Mynona. Salomo Friedlaender/
Mynona was a philosopher with books on Nietzsche and Schopenhauer, and an
original opus called Schöpferische Indifferenz; and a writer of grotesque fiction
published both in personal volumes and in all the main expressionist journals of
the time. The problem Kessler referred to was Ruest’s publication costs, and the
era was early post-revolutionary Germany, an era of remarkable social turmoil
and intellectual creativity—the latter triggered also by the abolition of censorship.
35
Harry Kessler, Diaries, 70.
26
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
Kessler’s note is one of the few written acknowledgments of the existence
of Der Einzige available today. Literary and intellectual histories of the time do
not remember the publication. It seems that for Kessler—and probably for many
intellectuals of the Weimar period who did not or chose not to remember it—
Der Einzige was just one of those many journals appearing after the war—“shooting
out of the ground” in what seemed to be a new era in German history.36
Kessler did not tell his readers whether he supported Ruest’s project. Maybe
he only intended to highlight a turn in the German literary landscape: the outbreak
of publications following an era of centralization and censorship, of which Ruest’s
project was an example. He noticed that the transition from the monarchical to the
bourgeois order produced chaos; human expression was not regulated; surprising
and unsettling points of view were voiced. Even established journals like Die
Aktion suddenly and radically changed their content. Reduced by war censorship
to a literary journal, the 1919 Die Aktion re-became the overt anarcho-communist
journal it had been before 1914.
The immediate post-revolutionary period marked a return of the radical Left
to the Berlin scene.37 The individualist anarchist Der Einzige belonged to this group
of the returning repressed, alongside Die Erde (The Earth, Ed. Walter Rilla, or
the more literary Die Erhebung (The Uprising, Ed. Alfred Wolfenstein); Das
36
37
Many of the “mushrooms” of the alternative Left were “Sprachröhre” of newly born organizations.
Der Arbeiterrat and Die Weltrevolution advocated the revolutionary politics of the Rätecommunists. The bi-monthly Der Freie Arbeiter, edited by Rudolf Oestrich, voiced the insights
of the German Communist Anarchist Federation; the weekly Die freie Jugend (edited by Ernst
Friedrich) was of the same anarchist orientation, but targeted the younger generation; and the
better known Die Freiheit, appearing twice a day during that period, was the organ of the USPD.
The weekly Der Marxist advocated the interests of an ecumenical socialist group, while Fritz
Kater’s and Max Winkler’s Der Syndikalist, a theoretical journal that reached 120 000 copies
in 1920, spoke in the name of the most successful anarchist movement in Germany, Die Freie
Arbeiter Union Deutschlands. See Aiga Seywald, Die Presse der sozialen Bewegungen, 34, 341.
On October 1918, the character type of Die Aktion changed. It became smaller, as if the journal
wanted to convey more on the same number of pages. It now had to say all the things it needed
to repress during the war years. The journal gave up publishing literature. Its idiom grew overtly
revolutionary, and already the November 16, 1918, issue identified Die Aktion as the organ of
the Antinationale Sozialisten Partei, whose goal was to build a socialist movement whose hands
were not stained with blood (see Ludwig, Bäumer, et al, “Aufruf der Antinationalen Sozialisten
Partei.”), and which was to struggle to make sure that change in German history would be
radical and irreversible: “Gelingt es unserem Henker Kapitalismus nochmals das erwachte
Volk einzuschläfern, gelingt der infame Schwindel mit der Nationalversammlung, die den
Geldschrank der Ausbeuter sichern soll, dann ist der 9. November umsonst gewesen” (Franz
Pfemfert, “Soldaten! Kameraden der A.S.P. Freunde der Aktion,” 587)
27
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
Forum (The Forum, Ed. Wilhelm Herzog), expressionistic and sympathetic to the
USPD;38 the Spartacist Der Revolutionär (The Revolutionary, Ed. Moritz Lederer),39
not expressionist but devoted to the arts and strongly anti-bourgeois; and the literary
revolutionary journal Umsturz und Aufbau (Overthrow and Reconstruction, Ed.
by Kurt Pinthus). There were satirical journals such as Faun—sympathetic to the
USPD and the Spartacist League; Jedermann sein eigner Fußball (Everyone's
Own Football, Ed. Wieland Herzfelde and John Heartfield), later Die Pleite (The
Bankruptcy)—a Dada journal to which Friedlaender/ Mynona also contributed;
and the Dada-communist (and anarchist, but mostly KPD sympathetic) Der
blutige Ernst, (The Bloody Earnest, edited by Carl Einstein and George Grosz).
Finally, there were two other specific individualist anarchist journals: Benedict
Lachmann’s Der individualistische Anarchist, “Organ der Vereinigung individualistischer Anarchisten,” (The Individualist Anarchist, Organ of the Gathering
of Individualist Anarchists), and the Hamburg-based monthly journal Ich (1920),
edited by Wallenstein (Jacob [Jack] Friedland), which would merge with the
Der Einzige of the 1920s.40
Kessler’s reference to mushrooms had a disqualifying connotation. Anarchism
was something a dandy aristocrat could accept on the canvas of an expressionist
painting or on the written page of a modernist poem, but it was too impure for
real-life politics, which required that a certain degree of organization be upheld.
His sense of order is also reflected in the observation “like mushrooms.” It means
more than enough. It also refers to an emergence out of a certain opportunity
(like mushrooms after the rain) and not to a tradition of what is truly important
in political life. Thus for an aristocrat, such opportunistic occurrences without
roots are doomed to be short lived and should be given limited attention.
And so it happened. Der Einzige died young and, it is not only the absence,
today, of any study—academic or otherwise—dedicated to Der Einzige that confirms
Kessler’s apprehensions, but the short life of the journal also anticipated that
German politics would take another path during its Weimar era. This path would
38
39
40
USPD, Unabhängige Sozialdemokratische Partei Deutschland (Independent German SocialDemocratic Party), was the short-lived and more radical faction of the German Social-Democratic
Party (SPD). It dissolved in 1922, most of its membership either returning to the SPD or entering
the ranks of its leftist rival, the KPD, the German Communist Party.
Voicing the ideas of the Spartacist League which then became the German Communist Party
(KPD).
See Aiga Seywald, Die Presse der sozialen Bewegungen, 96, 98, 169-170, 290.
28
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
be directed not toward building a diverse spectrum of peacefully cohabitating
leftist movements. None of the journals mentioned above survived into the 1920s.
As history approached the winter of 1933, the picture of the creative and truly
revolutionary Left of 1919 gradually faded into a bleak image of growing and
bureaucratized monoliths engaged in bitter clashes, growing more and more
indifferent to the radical Left’s visions of democracy.
One could assume that Ruest contacted Kessler not only because the latter was
an influential aristocrat capable of providing him with financial support, but also
because, as Nietzsche scholars, Kessler, Ruest and Friedlaender/ Mynona had been
allies. They had all fought to save the legacy of Nietzsche from the right-wing
politics of his sister Elisabeth.41 But even if they had been allies in the effort of
saving Nietzsche from becoming the inspiring mind of German nationalism and
war propaganda, Kessler’s and Der Einzige’s readings of Nietzsche agreed on few
issues. Der Einzige proposed a marriage of legacies that was not popular among
either Nietzsche or Stirner followers. Der Einzige did not back the aristocratic
individualism that the Count Kessler derived from the teachings of Zarathustra;
rather, it tried to integrate Nietzsche in the tradition of the radical German Left.
Here Der Einzige faced opposition not only from traditional Marxists, but also
from nineteenth-century Stirner conservatives like Mackay and Lachmann, who
refused to associate their inspirer with the “irrationalist” Nietzsche.
Der Einzige read Nietzsche as an individualist anarchist thinker and as a
follower of Stirner. Bearing this in mind, contacting another main collaborator of
the Nietzsche archive, Rudolf Steiner, for financial support would have seemed
a more propitious option. The future anthroposopher had been close to the Berlin
bohemians and championed a Stirner-Nietzsche synthesis. He was a friend of
Friedlaender/ Mynona, and, at least in his pre-religious years, regarded Stirner’s
Der Einzige und sein Eigentum as his philosophical alpha and omega.42 Moreover,
41
42
See, for example, Friedlaender/ Mynona’s review of Elizabeth’s book on the friendship between
Nietzsche and Wagner, S. Friedlaender, “Wagner und Nietzsche zur Zeit ihrer Freundschaft,
Elisabeth Förster Nietzsche,” Berliner Börsen Courier, Jg. 49, Beilage Nr. 38 v. 24.1. 1917, p. 5;
or Mynona’s satirical portrayal of her in his 1916 published story, Goethe spricht in den
Phonographen.
“For Rudolf Steiner, Max Stirner is an end and a beginning. Steiner judges all philosophies by
their nearness to the absolute egoism [sic] of Stirner,” writes Thomas Riley in Germany’s PoetAnarchist (73). See also Bernd A. Laska, “Die Individualanarchisten und Stirner.”
29
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
his reading of Nietzsche overlapped with that of Der Einzige. According to Steiner,
Nietzsche would have been a Stirner devotee, had he not died young.43
It is not clear whether Der Einzige found a Maecenas. Messages from the
editors suggest that the journal enjoyed a certain popularity for a while. Lisbeth
Exner speculates that Der Einzige found readers among the avant-garde circles,44
and Friedlaender/ Mynona looks back at Der Einzige as a journal with some
visibility.45 This visibility did not prevent however the journal from quickly
running into financial trouble. This was confirmed in Emil Szittya’s memoirs.
Szittya wrote that though Friedlaender/ Mynona was one of the most important
literary practitioners of the grotesque (as important as Paul Scheerbart), he was
at the same time a starving talent. About Ruest, Szittya wrote that he had poured
a lot of his own wealth into the journal.46
This “wealth” did not grant the survival of the weekly. Der Einzige’s first issue
was dated January 19, 1919,47 and its last, issue 28, bore the date November 1
of the same year. In the beginning it appeared once a week. The last issues no
longer kept up the initial pace. Lack of money shortened the life of the journal.
Thus, when Szittya called Ruest the only idealist of the individualist anarchist
movement he might have also been referring to Ruest’s clumsy handling of
financial matters. One cannot expect financial skills from a group that, according
to Szyttia, combined Stirnerianism with Scheerbartian “bohemian ideology.”48
Little is also known about the individualist anarchist circle around Ruest and
Mynona from which the publication emerged. The circle’s existence predates
that of the journal, and even the start of the war. The scarce information available
comes from sources that need to be taken with a grain of salt. There are two
such sources. One I already quoted above: the contested memoirs of Szittya. He
recalls that the circle, probably located in the Café des Westens, included Alfred
Richard Meyer, a literary figure with “a very good nose for what would be once
43
44
45
46
47
48
John Henry Mackay, Max Stirner, 603.
See Lisbeth Exner, Fasching als Logik, 182.
Quoted in Lisbeth Exner, Fasching als Logik, 176.
Emil Szittya, Das Kuriositäten Kabinett, 158-159.
The first issue appeared on the birthday of the third “patron saint” of the publication, Paul
Scheerbart.
Lehner quotes Szyttia in his book on the individualist anarchist origins of the Dada movement.
He finds Szyttia’s assumption dubious. Lehner argues that Friedlaender/ Mynona was the
theoretical head of the “cosmological trio” Baader-Scheerbart-Friedlaender in the bohemian
pre-war years (71-72).
30
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
important”; the anarchist painter Homayer; the poet and literary critic Ludwig
Rubiner, who helped Friedlaender/ Mynona publish his first short story; the sculptor
Otto Freundlich; and the future Dada artist Emmy Henning.49 Szittya’s account
is a pre-war account, because it designates Paul Scheerbart, “der lachende Heilige”
(the laughing saint) who died in 1915, as guru of the circle.50
The other account on the activity of Der Einzige covers the post-World War I
era. It belongs to Ludwig Marcuse. In his memoirs, Marcuse writes about his contact
with “the egotists” and how, under their influence, he discovered Stirner and realized
that the history of philosophy was much more diverse than its representation
in the university curriculum, which consisted of the provincial Greek-GermanChristian-idealist canon.51 Marcuse attended the meetings of the group, which
after the war included Gerhard Lehmann and other new faces. After the demise
of Der Einzige, Marcuse also participated in a four-day long Individualisten
Kongress.52 Marcuse recalls that meetings were no longer located in the famous
Café des Westens (which in the meantime had acquired bourgeois flavor) but in
the Café Innsbruck, which had more reasonable prices.
No other information on the group is available. All scholars who have written
on Der Einzige (Hartmut Geerken, Lisbeth Exner, Dieter Lehner, and Seth Taylor)
agree that the information on how Der Einzige came into being and how its two
editors collaborated is scarce, and that speculation is unavoidable. Marcuse does
not provide names, but one can assume that some of the people he met there
were contributors to Der Einzige such as Walter Bähr, A.W.M. Funder, Paul Gurk,
Otto Bahn-Höhne, Daimonides, Ludwig Hilbersheimer, Eduard Saenger, Rolf
Engert, Hans Pieper, and Ernst Roy. These names appear on a list publicized by
Ruest in the self-descriptive blurb of the last issue of Der Einzige (287). Facing
bankruptcy, Ruest emphasized that the effort was not in vain. During its shortlived existence, the journal had managed to breed a new generation of individualist
anarchists.
49
50
51
52
Emil Szittya, Das Kuriositäten Kabinett, 158-159.
Scheerbart died in poverty, which was ending of most of the members of the group. Alfred
Richard Meyer, who published some of the writings of the members of the group, did not get
rich in the publishing industry, Friedlaender/ Mynona recalls. See Salomo Friedlaender/ Mynona,
Ich (1871-1936), 67.
Ludwig, Marcuse, Mein zwanzigstes Jahrhundert, 65.
Ludwig Marcuse, Mein zwanzigstes Jahrhundert, 64.
31
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
The Cousins
Friedlaender/ Mynona scholars like Lisbeth Exner argue that, aside from
finances and the deafness of the period to radical democratic ideas, there was
another important reason as to why this project was so short-lived: the complicated
and sometimes tense relationship between its two editors and major contributors,
Ruest and Friedlaender/ Mynona. In this regard, Der Einzige was built on a
compromise. It was the brainchild of two philosophical projects that had touched
upon each other, but refused to converge. In a 1944 letter to his son and in the
wake of his brother-in-law’s death, Friedlaender/ Mynona writes that Ruest has
been his best friend since childhood, and that the only thing that stood between
them was their philosophical views.53
Friedlaender/ Mynona and Ruest were “Vetters” (uncle cousins) and brothersin-law.54 They grew up in middle-class Jewish families, studied philosophy, frequented the same circles, and helped each other materially and professionally.
They knew each other from childhood. Friedlaender/ Mynona was born in 1871.
Seven years older than Ruest, he served as a model for his younger cousin and
friend. However, once established in Berlin, it was the latter who, at least in the
beginning, played the role of initiator. According to Friedlaender/ Mynona, once
Ruest earned his doctorate (in Würzburg 1911) and started developing his own
philosophical ideas, the dynamics of their friendship changed. The relationship
between them became more and more one of “love and hate.”55 That did not lead
in any way to separation. In 1911 both were active contributors to Die Aktion.
Ruest was instrumental in Friedlaender/ Mynona’s move to Berlin. He hosted
his cousin, in-law and friend during his first days in the metropolis; introduced
him to the literary/ bohemian circles of the cafes on the Kurfürstendamm, a
milieu that had a great impact on the life and thoughts of the young philosopher
53
54
55
“Es klingt seltsam, aber Onkel Ernst fehlt mir. Er war mein allerintimster Freund, kannte jede
Falte. Trotz Altersunterschieds von rund sieben Jahren waren unsre Kindertage verflochten
und eigentlich war es nur die Philosophie, die in die Freundschaft eine Zwiespalt brachte.”
Quoted in Lisbeth Exner, Fasching als Logik, 176. One should also note that the brothers-inlaw did not call each other by their pen names. For family members, Friedlaender/Mynona’s
appellative was “Sali” or “Salomo.”
Friedlaender/Mynona’s favorite sister, Anna, married Ruest’s brother, Salomon Samuel.
Friedlaender/ Mynona, Ich, 63.
32
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
Friedlaender. It was in Berlin and in the spirit of anarchism that he also invented
his literary alter ego and pen-name Mynona.56
One can extrapolate the love-hate relationship between the two brothers-inlaw to Der Einzige, more specifically to the dynamics between the two sections of
the journal. Ruest was in charge of the main part, the “theoretical” one, while
the literary-humoristic supplement was under Friedlaender/ Mynona’s supervision.
And indeed, tensions between them were obvious. The question is how to interpret
them, especially when one has access only to Friedlaender/ Mynona’s memoirs.
Some caution in reading Friedlaender/ Mynona’s recollections is advisable.
His autobiography is rendered as the story of his Kantian awakening—more exactly,
of an awakening to the “magical” Kant discovered by Friedlaender/ Mynona through
Ernst Marcus. This awakening divides Friedlaender/ Mynona’s work. The partnership with Ruest belongs to the prehistory of his Kantian intellectual enlightenment.
The memoirs refer to this period as one in which his thought had chosen an
erroneous path; his soul had given way to temptation, and the explanation for
that lay in the fact that he was not able to discipline himself in the spirit of Kantian
teachings. The autobiography depicts a gradual conversion from “materialism,”
“exteriority,” and polarism to idealism and “interiority” and the order of “heliocentrism.” It tells the story of the anchoring of a singularity in a rational and
metaphysical I and of a gradual detachment from everything that is worldly.
Friedlaender/ Mynona built a contrast between himself and Ruest in terms of
a quarrel between philosophical nominalism and realism. Both drew on Stirner,
but Ruest understood individual sovereignty in a way that was for Friedlaender/
Mynona irrational and empirical.57 In contrast, Friedlaender/ Mynona was more
interested in a form for a universal understanding of the human, which at the
moment of writing his memoirs seemed superior to his Der Einzige period, a
56
57
“Eines Tages lud mich mein Vetter [Ruest] ein, in dem damals berühmtesten Bohemien Café
‘Großwahn’ bespitznahmt [Café des Westens], einen jungen russischen Lyriker aufzusuchen.
Diese Zusammenkunft inaugurierte eine Periode von acht Jahren, während deren ich das
bunte Leben des sog. Künstlervölkchens mitmachte.” Friedlaender/ Mynona, Ich, 64.
“Der Freund und Vetter suchte und fand diese Mitte, nach Stirners Rezept, in seinem Ich, aus
dem er jedoch etwas Irrationales zu machen schien, das mich unaufhörlich reizte; schon deshalb,
weil es ihm mehr zur Distanzierung als zur Annäherung diente […]. Es spielte sich zwischen
uns etwas ab wie der Streit des Realisten gegen den Nominalisten. Ich kultivierte die allgemeine
Menschheitsform des Ich, er dessen empirisch-konkreten Stoff, ohne dass er die Zusammengehörigkeit zu merken schien.” Friedlaender/ Mynona, Ich, 63-64.
33
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
period when he was not fully “converted” to the rationalist dogmatism of his later
years.58
In 1919, Friedlaender/ Mynona was in a phase of transition. He still framed his
writings in the bohemian-expressionist Stirner-Nietzsche postwar euphoria,59 but
at the same time, he started writing articles that signaled Marcus’s influence.60 He
had not yet become the apostle of the universal heliocentric self-centered order
and Ruest’s Stirner-inspired individualist anarchism still interested him. After
all, Friedlaender/ Mynona’s most influential opus, Schöpferische Indifferenz, a
work haunted by Stirner’s antihumanism, had appeared only a year before.
Friedlaender/ Mynona scholar Lisbeth Exner emphasizes that Friedlaender/
Mynona’s rejection of Stirner takes place only in letters and never in a publication.
Stirner is quoted only once in Schöpferische Indifferenz, but scholars like Dieter
Lehner have demonstrated the strong influence Stirner’s Der Einzige und sein
Eigentum had on Schöpferische Indifferenz. This position is also substantiated
by the many articles in which Friedlaender/ Mynona professed a vigorous antihumanist stance (opposed to his later “heliocentric humanism”) and denounced,
in the spirit of Stirner, Nietzsche and Ruest, the political construct of Mensch
(being human) a central theme of Der Einzige.
The creative philosophical dialogue between Friedlaender/ Mynona and Ruest,
whose best testimony is the publication of Der Einzige, ends in the early 1920s.
In the so-called second and third series of Der Einzige, Mynona is hardly present.61
58
59
60
61
Seth Taylor argues that the conversion happened in 1918 with the end of the war and with the
publication of Schöpferische Indifferenz. That would, however, contradict Friedlaender/Mynona’s
participation in Der Einzige, where, under the aegis of Stirner and Nietzsche, he wrote not only
for the supplement, but also philosophical pieces. I argue that, in 1919, Friedlaender/Mynona
was experimenting with the ideas of Stirner and Nietzsche for the last time, and that one can
talk of a true apostasy only after this collaborative has come to an end.
He writes not only for Der Einzige but also for other radical journals of the time.
See Dr S. Friedlaender, “Kant und die Freiheit. Nach Ernst Marcus.” Der Sturm, 11, February
1919.
Without Friedlaender/ Mynona on the editorial board, Ruest tried to revive Der Einzige first
in 1920 as a series of brochures titled “Einzelschriften für die Mitglieder des Stirnerbunds.”
Three such booklets appeared: Rolf Engert (Hrsg.), Max Stirner’s 1834 essay, Über Schulgesetze;
Reinhard Hanko, Dissoziativismus; Paul Cohn, Gemütseregungen als Krankheitsursachen
(probably a reprint of the two articles already published in Der Einzige). None of these issues
is available. In 1921, six issues of Der Einzige appeared in small format, mainly written by
Ruest. And then again, a try in 1923-4 that led to issues 1 to 3, and another one, in 1925,
resulting in two issues. In 1938, while already in exile in Paris, Ruest attempted another revival
but under a new name: Die Empörung. Eine Zeitschrift für Mündige. According to Geerken,
34
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
Lisbeth Exner quotes a letter by Friedlaender/ Mynona that highlights the ensuing
gap between the editors. In this letter, Friedlaender/ Mynona declares bombastically
that all his life he had done everything he could not relate to Ruestian individualism in other fashion than the grotesque.62 Exner emphasizes that Friedlaender/
Mynona and Ruest became closer again in their Parisian exile. Their relationship
was, however, more like a cohabitation in contradiction, a fragile truce of mutual
tolerance imposed upon them by the hard times they experienced as refugees from
Nazi persecution.
A key contributor to Der Einzige was Gerhard Lehmann. He represented the
voice of the younger generation. His name stood among those of young intellectuals
who had been schooled in disobedience by Der Einzige. He was only 23 at the
time and a dedicated disciple of Ruest. As student and enthusiastic individualist
anarchist, he was willing to go beyond the practice of writing articles for the
journal. He organized a student individualist anarchist group and a discussion
group associated with Der Einzige, named Gesellschaft für Individualistische Kultur
(Society for Individualistic Culture), also known as the Stirnerbund.
Lehmann wrote polemic articles and organized and reported on the activities
of the Gesellschaft. Like Friedlaender/ Mynona, however, possibly under his
influence, Lehman later underwent a Kantian conversion himself. In the postWorld War II period he became one of Germany’s best-known Kant editors and
scholars. The break with Ruest and the conversion seemed to start as early as 1920.
After Lehmann’s defection, Ruest inaugurated another discussion group in the
1920s—called Verein der Einzige (Union Der Einzige), later Individualistenbund—
with which he organized the aforementioned “Individualistencongreß.” Lehmann’s
conversion triggered, as in Friedlaender/ Mynona’s case, an act of distancing
from his “Stirner years.” Bernd Laska documents that, in later autobiographical
accounts, Lehmann regarded his passion for Stirner as a youthful malaise.63
62
63
the editor of the 1980 reprint of Der Einzige, the first issue was prepared but never made it to
the printer.
Lisbeth Exner, Fasching als Logik, 176.
Bernd A. Laska, “Von Stirner zu Kant: Gerhard Lehmann” Der Einzige. 4 (12), November
2000, 5-16.
35
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
The Times
Should this desertion from individualist anarchism by two core contributors
of Der Einzige be read as unconnected to the financial troubles of the journal?
Or should one read it as a sign of the times? And if one can blame the “times,”
how far can one go beyond what I have already assumed: a tendency toward
centralization within the Left?
The relative initial popularity of the journal indicates the receptivity to radical
democratic projects during this period. The short life of the project, however,
testifies to the opposite. I mentioned the names of other journals that proposed
alternative agendas of the German Left. Almost all of them ran into financial
problems and lost their audience even before the economic crisis of the early
1920s. 1919 was the year of their glory. It was a year in which the German political
imaginary, or at least part of it, was bold enough to explore radical political transformations with the feeling that these ideas were closer to becoming reality than
ever before. Almost all of these journals disappeared once the period of unrest
was over and the Left consolidated its positions. Its two main alternatives became
the reformist-statist SPD and a Leninist/ Stalinist KPD. The possibility of a “third
way” of doing politics from the Left was lost or literally murdered, as it happened
with the leader of the USPD Hugo Haase in 1920.
In its beginnings, the German revolution of 1918-1919 was a spontaneous
act of revolt. It constituted an event that did not carry with it a clear meaning other
than a will to change. Investing it with meaning was a post-factum practice. Its
causes and goals were signified and “understood”; representatives emerged and
the revolution was completed. Though a highbrow philosophical-literary journal,
Der Einzige tried to respond to the turmoil of early 1919 and thus represent the
unfolding events in its own idiom. Its first issue was dated January 19, 1919. The
first phase of the revolutionary wave was over. The republic was proclaimed, the
new structures of power and the new faces that would dominate the first part of the
Weimar political terrain had already gained prominence and had begun eliminating their most challenging competitors. Four days before, Karl Liebknecht
36
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
and Rosa Luxemburg—two important figures of German leftist radicalism—
had been assassinated at the orders of the SPD.64
Looking back at the historical context, one notices the delay with which Der
Einzige tried to propose its own radical social project. And one can speculate
that theory is always too fast or too slow. It is too fast in the sense that, as many
“anti-totalitarian” thinkers argue, the facts of life are more complicated and slower
than revolutionary paper visions. But at the same time, some theory, perhaps
the truly relevant, can be too slow. This theory is a genre of retrospection, one
that looks perhaps too close at facts. As such it arrives too late to influence the facts
of life, and functions only as a machine of appropriation, rationalizing what has
already happened.
Der Einzige generated this second type of theory and by the time its first
issue circulated, the future of Weimar Germany had already been settled. The
unstable and paradoxical coalitions between reactionaries and reformists had
already been built. History had moved faster than the editors’ words on paper.
What they and so many other journals were left with was a look at a fait accompli,
and only the opportunity to protest against an unjust turn of events that contradicted their political dreams. The spirit of revolt that had largely been swept off
the streets of Berlin in 1919 by proto-fascist paramilitary groups survived in
intellectual positions. The first issue of Der Einzige appeared on the day of the
first postwar elections for the National Assembly. This date marked the end of
the period in which all political options were on the table. These elections conferred
legitimacy to the new power structures. The return to normality had begun. It
was a chilling return as this normality was in many ways reminiscent of the prewar context as Marcuse’s experiences discussed in the Introduction suggest.
Detlev Peukert also reads January 19 as marking the end of the short-lived
revolutionary era.65 Peukert highlights that the important resolutions regarding
form of government, establishment of the main nuclei of power and their elites had
already been reached in the period that preceded the appearance of Der Einzige.
This period was November 9, 1918 – January 19, 1919. These new and old elites
had decided to follow a constitutionalist path toward the emancipation of workers
and called for the suppression of the Councils (Räte) movement. Having Russia
64
65
See note 38.
Detlev Peukert, Weimar Germany, 28-33.
37
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
as a counter-model of chaos, the president of the newly born German republic,
Friedrich Ebert, set order as his highest priority. He focused on the achievement
of limited political and economic goals, condoned administrative continuity, and
joined forces with the leaders of the imperial army. The period that followed
the elections, in which Der Einzige saw the light of print, was, Peukert argues,
one of disappointments, when the pernicious decisions of the previous period
became apparent. The forces of change were split and their power limited. Ebert
started his war against leftist radicalism again; the conservative right realized
that it had more power than it had expected, and social frustration increased.
Der Einzige positioned itself both against the Ebert reformist government
and the revolutionary communism of the Räte-movement. In the context of this
divided Left, the journal looked for the third leftist way, as did many other radical
journals and movements of the time. In an era in which the political could no
longer provide space for reconciliation, Der Einzige argued for the abolition of
the political as a framework for organized power struggle. And it is this quest
for an alternative—one understood, however, not within the traditional political
framework, but starting with the canceling of the “rules” of the political game
itself—that makes Der Einzige’s intervention so interesting today in the aftermath
of the Cold War and the Occupy movements, when the Left has exhausted the
two strategies with which it had widely engaged: reform and revolution, and has
still not clearly figured out what comes after capitalism.
Der Einzige was an “unhappy consciousness,” contemplating in disappointment
the political debates of the post-revolutionary period. Its displeasure was, nevertheless, not so much caused by the proposed or adopted political solutions, but
by the idea of “solution” itself, by the closure and the warping of the political
imaginary itself. The opening that followed the revolt of 1918 and the fall of
the monarchy was too hastily harnessed into yet another vision of order. The future
of a community, open for a few weeks, was rearrested and community redefined.
The same individuals who had fought for freedom from an oppressive state
were too quick in figuring out other monopolies of power to contain revolt, as if
freedom had been an unbearable existential challenge.
The abundance of radical literature in this period, trying to resignify the arrested
moment of revolt, continued a pre-war commitment to change. In an article on
the origins of World War I, John Zerzan argues that containing this pre-war
revolutionary activity constituted one of the main drives that brought Europe to
38
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
war in 1914.66 To understand how Der Einzige’s ideas were prepared in the prewar era, one needs to return to the German/ Prussian imperial times and to the
development of radical voices among leftist intellectuals. For Der Einzige, that
defining pre-war moment was the Stirner Renaissance occurring around 1890.
This event proved influential not only for the German literary bohemian and avantgarde circles, but also for the whole socialist movement. Der Einzige was the last
significant echo of this Renaissance, and Anselm Ruest its final prophet.
The Renaissance
The importance of the Stirner Renaissance rests, however, not only in the fact
that a forgotten philosopher, Max Stirner, and his opus, Der Einzige und sein
Eigentum, became a philosophical bestseller and influenced thinkers of both the
Left and the Right, from Gustav Landauer and the Dada groups to Carl Schmitt
and Mussolini. The Stirner Renaissance marked a renewal of German (and, to a
certain extent, European) anarchism. It triggered the birth of the individualistanarchist movement and delivered concepts that helped the middle-class, the
artistic avant-garde and the metropolitan bohemia to design their participation
in radical politics.
On a broader scale, it contributed to the intellectualization of German anarchism,
which until then had employed the practice-oriented idiom of anarcho-syndicalism
and skilled-worker centered movements. Individualist anarchism was thus instrumental in de-proletarianizing the Left, and offered the bourgeois the chance to
fight the discourses of its own class from inside. It provided the middle class
with increased legitimacy to question the values it adopted during the imperial
era, and to test its pragmatism, its repressive moralism, its programmatic political
narrow-mindedness, and its refusal to be aware of its role of oppressed and oppressor
within the mechanisms of the organization of life and labor under capitalism.
With individualist anarchism, the social figure replacing the proletariat as the
nemesis of the bourgeoisie became the rebel and the bohemian—a figure that
mixed both sub-proletarian features with middle-class ones.
In his book on the impact of anarchism on the avant-garde, Hubert Van den
Berg suggests that, if one wants to better grasp insightful forms of bourgeois
66
John Zerzan, Elements of Refusal, 147.
39
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
class treason, one has to understand the bourgeoisie not so much in terms of
income, property and work relations, but in broader cultural terms, values and
social practices.67 This assumption is in line with the cultural turn discussed in
the Introduction and this turn’s weakening of the link between class identity and
legitimacy to call for and even enforce social justice. Helmut Kreuzer suggests
that the bohemian be regarded as the bourgeois liberated from his or her
“Bürgerlichkeit.” Van den Berg also indicates that working-class anarchism,
in contrast to the bohemian one, was more politically organized, more focused
on the state system and its institutions of physical and corporeal exploitation.
Bohemian anarchism was more interested in disciplining through censorship,
morality, social codes, and especially sexual repression.68 As I will argue in the
next chapter, this “cultural approach” did not make the protest of the rebellious
middle class less political. What it did was to inaugurate a tactics of resistance
that would be continued by various socially concerned thinkers of the twentieth
century, who aimed at rebelling not only against a state imagined as a material
embodiment of power, but more importantly against the practices of containment
encoded in the social-moral-cultural aspects of life.
The Stirner Renaissance also endowed the philosophical language of the Left
with more depth. It made it more sensitive to the construction of human subjectivity,
to the evils of organized movements, to its neglect of the individuality of the worker
and, as Seth Taylor argues, it interested the Left in Nietzsche. It “provided an
alternative basis for interpreting Nietzsche other than Julius Langbehn’s influential Rembrandt als Erzieher (Rembrandt as Educator), which appropriated
Nietzsche for the cause of nationalism and Germany’s conservative revolution.”69
Several scholars have also focused on the impact of the Renaissance on the
literary and artistic innovators of the period. From the naturalists of the early 1890s
to the Dadas of the 1920s, almost every prominent figure had read Stirner’s Der
Einzige und sein Eigentum or one of the many compilations of his work circulating in that period. David Weir emphasizes that even the young James Joyce
was under the individualist anarchist spell, due to Benjamin Tucker, the main
promoter of Stirner in the English-speaking world.70
67
68
69
70
Hubert van der Berg, Avantgarde und Anarchismus, 95.
Hubert van der Berg, Avantgarde und Anarchismus, 96.
Seth Taylor, Left Wing Nietzscheans, 143.
David Weir, Anarchy and Culture, 213.
40
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
The Bohemia
Among the German Stirner enthusiasts we find the leading figures of the
bohemia. And that should not come as a surprise, argues Julius Bab, the chronographer of the Berlin bohemia, since Stirner himself, the theoretician, as he puts
it, of “true anarchism,” was one of them. Stirner was a habitué of the radical
coffee house culture. He had his “Stammtisch” (regulars’ table) at Hippel pub
(on Friedrichstrasse), where the Young Hegelians met. It was this milieu that
inspired and helped him develop his ideas, Bab argues, because, in Bab’s
opinion, the bohemia is nothing but a peaceful attempt at practical anarchism,
and the creation of a disobedient and self-governing group of people outside of
the organized society. 71
The concept of bohemia, Kreuzer argues, points to a subculture of intellectuals that is individualist in organization and violent in symbolic praxis. It includes
individuals with artistic ambitions whose politics are aimed at undermining the
bourgeois liberal state. Kreuzer emphasizes that bohemia is not an artistic category,
but a sociological one. He believes that the life of the bohemian is more important than his or her oeuvre. Their art—poems, paintings, music, etc.—is an
instrument, a practice subsumed to the political project of permanent rebellion.
That which constitutes the bohemian, Erich Mühsam explains, is, negatively,
the result of a revolted and revolting spirit. Positively, it is the impulse to live
dangerously, away from the protection of norms or social customs.
Neither poverty nor inconstancy is the decisive criterion for being bohemian,
but the urge for freedom that finds the courage to break social bonds and create
the forms of life that set the least resistance to one’s inner development.72
According to Mühsam, radicals wanted to build an anti-world that hosted
oppositional practices of living that challenged the legacy of the obedient subject
of the imperial state. This is why they identified with the underworld and praised
71
72
“Denn was ist ‘Boheme’ im Grunde anders als ein friedlicher Versuch zu praktischem Anarchismus,
d.h. zur Bildung eines unbeherrschten Lebenskreises außerhalb der staatlich organisierten
Gesellschaft.” Julius Bab, Die Berliner Bohème, 23.
”Weder Armut noch Unstetigkeit ist entscheidendes Kriterium für die Boheme, sondern
Freiheitsdrang, der den Mut findet, gesellschaftliche Bindungen zu durchbrechen und sich die
Lebensformen zu schaffen, die der eigenen inneren Entwicklung die geringsten Widerstände
entgegensetzen.” Erich Mühsam, Unpolitische Erinnerungen, 491.
41
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
its crooks, prostitutes, criminals, and beggars. They looked for the most authentic
and embodied forms of rebellion that would allow them to own their lives in a
Stirnerian sense and be singular. The hatred of centralized institutions, the rejection
of the political, the undermining of normative social practices, the emphasis on
social self-help and direct social action, the cult of autonomy, and the will to design
forms of living free from institutional authority were, according to Linse, some
of the principles of the anarchist movement and the bohemia.73
Kreuzer highlights that individualist anarchism as well as anarcho-communism
were the main political views that the bohemians shared. Very often the same
person will share both these visions at different stages of his or her intellectual
development (Erich Mühsam, Gustav Landauer, or many of the Dadas). Many
of the bohemians were one way or another attached to the socialist movement,
and some were instrumental in the efforts to redefine it from inside.
It should come as no surprise that almost concomitant with the Stirner
Renaissance a major split within the German socialist movement occurred. The
split officially happened in 1891, and led to the formation of a series of splinter
groups (including many anarchist ones) which were known under the broad title
of independent socialists. Some of the keywords of this split resonated with
individualist anarchism and the bohemia’s cultural practices: decentralization
and individualism, and the protest against the turning bourgeois of the socialist
movement. The divide followed the SPD’s return to legality. Ten years of proscription under Bismarck’s Sozialistengesetz (October 1878) had made many
socialist activists believe that changing the world was possible only via subversive
and revolutionary acts. The reformist, parliamentary and compromise-open politics
of the SPD, aiming at building a mass party, were regarded as a pernicious
reinforcement of the status quo. Radical intellectuals of the Left realized that
the loose forms of organization practiced during the period of prohibition proved
more democratic and ethically more acceptable than the idea of a rank and file
movement, organized hierarchically, like a military structure, on the principle
of authority which socialism adopted in 1919.
Many German naturalist writers also opposed the mainstream reformist party
politics of the SPD. Naturalists were not bohemians, even if toward the end of
the century their writings became more linked to literary decadence and their
73
Ulrich Linse, Organisierter Anarchismus im deutschen Kaiserreich von 1871, 97.
42
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
subject matter shifted from the working class to the Lumpenproletariat and other
outsiders of society, embodying the abnormal and the delinquent. Their radicalism,
however, still functioned in many ways within the intellectual paradigm of the
Enlightenment. The rational homo constructor was still at the center of their
understanding of political agency. They just doubted that traditional structures
of organization were the right tools to materialize their dreams, especially as
embodied in the capitalism with an imperial face of pre-war Germany.
The naturalists were the first generation of intellectuals to experience the
Stirner-Nietzsche impact. Their individualism questioned the liberating potential
of organized battalions of workers. Many trusted neither the party-controlled
working class nor its elites. Naturalists advocated a free floating intellectual as
a corrective voice to the abuses of organization. Only a few of them, however,
made a step further to question the idea of organization itself (and even fewer the
problematic nature of being free-floating). Most of them criticized organized
structures with the hope that a certain amount of reflection could fix the problem.
Some grew more radical, assuming more thoroughly the consequences of the
Stirner-Nietzsche critique of the rational man. Those who embarked on questioning reason itself and the universalism of intellectual discourse found a
refuge in the bohemian circles.74
I argue that bohemia played an important role in the crystalizing of the
positions of Der Einzige. The obvious reason is that many of its contributors
were part of it. But there is an intellectual link as well. For Der Einzige, the
bohemia constituted a pre-war model for understanding and reinventing the
idea of community and for putting into practice anarchist ideas, experimenting
in the realms of both art and life. Bohemia embodied a living community that
resembled Stirner’s community of egotists.75 It was here that men and women
tried out “total anarchism” and the undoing of structures of authority. Linse
highlights that anarchism was practiced not only with the purpose of challenging human interaction. Revolt was practiced at all levels of life: morality,
74
75
A proof of the fact that bohemia is such a place of refuge is the “Abkehrromane” of many
former realists and naturalists. Kreuzer highlights that very often this turn was regarded as
unjustified. Intellectuals allegedly turned away from socialism (often under the influence of
Nietzsche and aristocratic individualism) more because it was fashionable (292). Heinrich
Mann unfairly criticized this attitude in Im Schlaraffenland, calling them converts of March
1890 (Quoted in Kreuzer 293). Salon anarchism also became trendy during these years.
Julius, Bab, Die Berliner Bohème, 39.
43
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
manners, conduct, thinking, feeling, food, clothing, and love. No wonder then,
Linse concludes, that most of these bohemians found a philosophical speaker of
their ideas in Stirner.76
The Stirner Renaissance grew in the fertile environment of the literary café.
Der Schwarze Ferkel and Café des Westens in Berlin or the later Café Innsbruck
(where the Der Einzige team convened), Café Stephanie in Munich, and Cabaret
Voltaire in Zurich were such physical and intellectual alternative public spaces.
Der Hippel of the 1840s, like its later turn of the century replicas cited above,
were laboratories “of all libertarian ideas, all forms of bold critique and free
thought.”77 Theo Kneubühler also shows that the café became an imago mundi
in which the radical individualist could experiment with his or her egotist beliefs
and cultivate his singularity both externally and internally. It was an island of
liberated public life, in which social relations could be made or un-made at every
moment. It was the quintessential place of transition in which men and women
joined thoughts and projects that could not even be envisioned and even less put
into practice in a different place.78
Some of the notorious Stirner (and Nietzsche) inspired bohemians were
Stanislaw Przybyszewski, the leading figure at the Schwarze Ferkel pub (The
Black Hog), author of the famous novel Satans Kinder (Children of Satan)79
and proclaimer of “unconditioned and unrefrained abandonment, revaluation,
and destruction of the enclosures of the bourgeois brain, as well as all barriers
76
77
78
79
See Ulrich Linse, Organisierter Anarchismus im deutschen Kaiserreich von 1871, 98-99. In
an article dedicated to the presence of artists and writers in the Tessin and the Monte Verita
libertarian colonies, Theo Kneubühler highlights that Stirner’s influence on the literary bohemia
and the avant-garde was not only in terms of positions, but also inspired a certain style of
engagement. The work of predecessors was engaged polemically always avoiding identification,
and concentrating on one’s self. This attitude created a culture of philological disrespect, the
praise of textual theft and of genius in everybody. Under the influence of Stirner and Nietzsche,
Kreuzer writes, “Alle Literaturcafés in Berlin, München und Wien und noch in ein paar
anderen Großstädten wimmelten damals von ‘Übermenschen’” (quoted in Kneubühler 150).
Julius, Bab, Die Berliner Bohème, 25.
“Der Boheme war Einzelgänger, sein Ort war das Café in der Großstadt, also ein oeffentlicher
Bereich, wo er jederzeit hinkonnte, weg konnte, wo er Beziehungen frei wählen konnte, je nach
Stunde, Absicht oder Zustand. […] Das Café ist der Inbegriff eines transitorischen Ortes, einer
Durchgangsstation, Verbindlichkeit oder Unverbindlichkeit frei wählbar ist, wo das was im
Kopf ist und nur dort für Stunden ‘Wirklichkeit’ werden konnte, da es im Anderen Widerhall
fand, weil dieser andere ähnliche Ideen, Gedanken, Bilder mit sich herumtrug, Ideen, die sonst
nirgends Wirklichkeit werden konnten.“ Theo Kneubühler, “Die Künstler und Schriftsteller
und das Tessin (von 1900 bis zur Gegenwart),” 151.
Regarded as the promoter of Satanism in literature.
44
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
of morality, society, and authority for the purpose of liberating one’s ‘individuality’.”80 There was Hugo Kersten, the promoter of impertinentism,81 who
attacked the institution of art and the cult of self-discipline of the bourgeois subject;82
Conrad Froelich, the promoter of the poetics of explosion and of the virtues of
coarseness (Grobheit) (especially after 1897);83 the Dadaists Johannes Baader and
Raoul Hausmann, with whom Friedlaender/ Mynona tried to publish a journal
in 1915 titled Erde; and the chief animators of the Cabaret Voltaire, Hugo Ball
and Tristan Tzara.84
John Henry Mackay
At the origin of the Stirner Renaissance was John Henry Mackay (1864-1933).
In his memoirs, Szittya calls Mackay “the founder of individualist anarchism.”85
Although he never wanted it, Mackay became a bridge between Stirner and the
literary modernists. He was one of the transitional literary naturalists who never
truly grasped the project of the anarchist bohemia though he was a regular at
Café des Westens. He opposed the Stirner-Nietzsche fusion adopted by modernist
circles, and his understanding of individualist anarchism, a term that he coined,
was different from that of Ruest and his cohort.
In spite of his Anglo-Saxon name, Mackay was German and wrote only in
German. He republished Stirner’s forgotten Der Einzige und sein Eigentum in 1911
80
81
82
83
84
85
“[…] unbedingte und besinnungslose Selbst-Entgrenzung, Umwertung, Zertrümmerung der
Schranken des bürgerlichen Gehirns, aller Schranken von Moral, Gesellschaft, Autorität überhaupt zwecks Freisetzung von ‘Individualität’” (quoted in Fähnders 158).
Also influenced by Friedlaender/ Mynona; Die Aktion published his “Impertinentist Manifesto”
in 1915 (Die Aktion, 35/36, September 4, 1915, 48-450, signed A. Undo). The impertinentists
separated from expressionism because they no longer regarded themselves as a literary movement:
“Wir tun so, als ob wir Maler, Dichter oder sonst was wären, aber wir sind nur und nichts als
mit Wollust frech” (449).
”Die Selbstdisziplinierungsideologie des Bürgertums erforderte die rigide Anpassung an das
Bestehende. Sie bildete Autoritätshörigkeiten Untertanenmentalität heraus, forderte aber auch
sexualfeindlichen Triebverzicht” (Quted in Lehner 78).
See Walter Fähnders, Anarchismus und Literatur, 61.
Tzara’s Manifeste Dada (1918) is a hymn of praise to the I, Van den Berg emphasizes (68). Tzara’s I,
like that of Stirner, should liberate itself from external determinations, create and control his
or her reality. This cult of the I will go as far as to cajole the I to become the producer of its own
signifiers. Van den Berg suggests that, in his 1916 Dada manifesto, Ball confessed that he had
become so radical that he did not want to use the words others invented. He wanted to create
his own vocabulary, “mein eigener Unfug” (69).
Das Kuriositäten Kabinett, 155.
45
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
and edited a volume of Stirner’s “minor” texts (1898). He wrote a monograph on
Stirner in 1898, and a series of influential Stirner-informed Bildungsromane. The
most influential was Die Anarchisten (1891), which can be regarded as marking
the birth of German individualist anarchism. Another was Der Freiheitssucher
(The Freedom Seeker, 1920), which he considered the capstone of his revolutionary
thought, but which was less successful than his previous novel.
In contrast to Der Einzige, Mackay’s positions were much more tributary to
nineteenth-century rationalism. He belonged to literary naturalist groups like
Durch, which included Bruno Wille, Johannes Schlaf, and Gerhart Hauptmann,
and to the intellectual community around the Hart brothers. His turn to individualist
anarchism happened while in England, probably under the influence of Benjamin
Tucker.86 Mackay also never thought of himself as an organizer. Unlike other
anarchists of his generation, such as Gustav Landauer, he isolated himself from
people and crowds. He limited his praxis to writing books. The only organizing
effort he managed to complete was a reunion of individualist anarchists in Berlin
in 1910 (co-organized with the editor Bernhard Zack). This group decided not
to do any propaganda among the working class, but only among the educated.87
Thus on August 12, 1910, the “Vereinigung individualistischer Anarchisten”
(The union of individualist anarchists) was founded, and in May 1911 its first
newsletter appeared in 1,000 copies (it would decrease dramatically; the next
issues were down to 200 copies, and it ceased to exist in October). The Vereinigung
dissolved in 1913 and was shortly revived by Benedict Lachmann after the war.
The publication of Mackay’s Die Anarchisten in 1891 triggered a break within
the anarchist movement, between individualist and communist anarchists. A
debate on organization and revolutionary politics ensued that continued over
the years and proved to be a central issue for Der Einzige too. Mackay used the
term “individualist anarchism” to distinguish his Stirner-inspired position from
an anarchism understood through the concepts of Bakunin and Marx. Anarchism
could only be individualist, Mackay argued, because freedom was individual, not
the same for two people. He admitted that the phrase “individualist anarchism”
86
87
Mackay argued that he had “discovered” Stirner all by himself. American scholar Thomas Riley
questions Mackay’s claim. According to Riley, the Americans were the ones who rediscovered
Stirner, and “it was Benjamin Tucker who converted John Henry Mackay from the revolutionary,
communistic anarchism of Europe to the non-violent, non communistic anarchism that had
grown out of American individualism” (58).
See Ulrich Linse, Organisierter Anarchismus im deutschen Kaiserreich von 1871, 82.
46
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
was tautological. True, unrestrained individualism was anarchism, and an anarchism
that was radically anti-authoritarian was individualist. The use of the pleonastic
phrase “individualist anarchism” was necessary only because a faction of the
communist movement had mistakenly appropriated the term anarchism for itself.
An intellectual phenomenon like Der Einzige revealed, however, how “individualist anarchism” slipped out of Mackay’s hands; how he could not control
the rereading of Stirner by the bohemia, and the fusion with Nietzsche’s ideas.
Mackay fought hard to keep individualist anarchism within the confines of his
interpretations of Stirner. In numerous texts, he aimed at demonstrating the
incompatibility between Stirner and Nietzsche and Stirner and bohemianism. In
his Stirner monograph, he described this tension in terms of an incompatibility
of intellectual temperament. The ironic-analytic mind of Stirner could have only
few things in common with Nietzschean flamboyance or with the passionate style
of the Young Hegelians frequenting the Hippel (among them Karl Marx).
Aside from his rationalist and anti-bohemian positions,88 Mackay’s hagiographic approach to Stirner was also problematic for many individualist anarchists,
Ruest included.89 Ruest criticized Mackay’s effort to turn Stirner into a prophetic
figure as the communist movement did with Marx. Here is a sample of Mackay’s
encomiastic approach. In a poem he presents Stirner as a “genius unrecognized
88
89
Although he wrote unconventional literature under the pseudonym Sagitta dedicated to his
passion for young boys and was one of the first activists for gay rights, Mackay was definitely
anti-bohemian. In his memoirs, Mühsam portrays Mackay as “der konventionellste Mensch”
who visited the Café des Westens. For Mackay, everyday individualist anarchism meant solitary,
distant and well-mannered behavior. Manners and decorum, he thought, were the products of
the individual’s effort to create an autonomous zone around him/ herself. Mühsam hints
ironically that the end product of such an approach to life could be nothing but bourgeois
dandyism. Er “kleidete sich in sorgfältig durchdachte Unauffälligkeit [and] verhielt sich in jeder
Situation pedantisch korrekt” (Mühsam Unpol 541). Mackay read Stirner’s work into his life.
He saw Stirner as an ascetic philosopher, parsimonious in expression, ironic and extremely lucid.
Nr. 3 (7) of the new series of Der Einzige (August 1999) is dedicated to John Henry Mackay.
Most articles question Mackay’s originality and the way in which he administered the memory
of Stirner. (See the articles by Bernd A. Laska, “John Henry Mackay’s Stirner-Archiv in Moskau”;
Rolf Engert, “Mackay’s Stirner-Biographie und die Notwendigkeit ihrer Ergänzung,” and Mirko
Jeleusich, “John Henry Mackay. Ein individualistischer Anarchist Stirnerscher Provenienz?”)
Thomas Riley emphasizes that the philosophers of the turn of the century did not appreciate
Mackay’s analysis of Stirner’s work. They only appreciated his biographical research and his
work as editor of the Kleinere Schriften (72).
47
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
by his century,” whose “wisdom” has triggered Mackay’s awakening, and in turn
Mackay has given Stirner back to humankind.90
Paradoxically, Mackay wrote about the unsystematic nature of Stirner’s thought
and about the error of turning his writings into a-historical dogmas. He argued that
Stirner’s philosophy is not a system that can build a school of thought which can
then generate canonic readings of Stirner and consolidate this system. “Each
has to learn from him what he or she wants, without ever becoming his student
in the narrow sense of the word.” Because if one wanted to become such a student,
Stirner himself would reject him or her and accuse them of idolatry.91
Mackay’s writings were, however, the first to contradict these assumptions.
Everything he wrote after Die Anarchisten was part of a project to create a certain
canon of interpretation of Stirner’s work aimed at intimidating the bohemian
pro-Nietzsche faction. The pre-war quarrels with Ruest (which toned down during
the second half of 1919—when it became clear that the individualist anarchist
movement could not afford internal tensions) also stemmed from Mackay’s
orthodoxy and from the fact that the two belonged to different generations of
intellectuals. In the introduction to the third edition (1910) of his monograph on
Stirner, Mackay had only negative things to say about Ruest.92 The generational
conflict was manifest. Mackay’s book on Stirner was descriptive, centered on
facts, slightly positivist, and aiming to establish the truth. In contrast, Ruest’s
Max Stirner. Leben, Weltanschauung, Vermächtnis (1907), which Mackay bashed,
was idiosyncratic. It interpreted the life and work of Stirner through the idea of
rebellion—Ruest’s interpretation itself being an act of rebellion.
Ruest’s reaction to Mackay was not friendly either. He reproached Mackay
that he had transformed Stirner into an idol, and had placed his ideas in “heaven.”93
In an article published in Die Aktion he also ironized Mackay’s poetry presenting
it as pompous and making use of unconvincing calls for armed rebellion.94 A
90
91
92
93
94
[…] Genius, den sein Jahrhundert/ Nie die arme schloss/ O Genius, hinabgesunken/ Wärst du
in das Schweigen der Nacht?/ Nein – meine Lippe hat getrunken/ Hat sie – ich bin erwacht./
Unsterblicher! Schauernd begrüße/ Ich dich aus der Nacht um mich her. Quoted in Walter,
Fähnders. Anarchismus und Literatur, 93.
John Henry Mackay, Max Stirner, 131.
John Henry Mackay, Max Stirner, 21.
Sigrid Hauff, “Maßnahmen des Verschwindens. Die Familien Friedlaender und Ruest im
französischen Exil,” 92.
“Seine Gedichte von viel trotzigem Heldenmut, von Schlachtruf und Schwerterklingen, von
verzweifeltem Ausharren und einsamem Überleben, von herrlicher Selbstgenügsamkeit und
48
1. Individualist Anarchism in the Post‐World War I Period
polemic between the two never ensued, but one might speculate that the fact that
Der Einzige never called itself individualist anarchist also expressed this tension.
The “Mackay” brand of individualist anarchism also resurged after the war in
Benedict Lachmann’s journal Der individualistische Anarchist. Lachmann, like
Mackay and Tucker, followed the rationalist anti-Nietzsche path.95 Like Mackay,
Lachmann did not attempt to pose as original thinker, but adopted the role of
canonic promoter and explicator. In a book that traced the origins of individualist
anarchism in the literature and practices of ancient Athens’s sophists (Protagoras,
Nietzsche, Stirner. Platz dem Egoismus!), he followed Mackay in stressing the
impossibility of a Stirner-Nietzsche synthesis. His revolutionary theory was based
on Tucker’s call for the abolition of the four state monopolies, but filtered through
a practical mind that, unlike Der Einzige, could not radically distance itself from
social and political reformism. In a polemical article, titled “Die Übergangssozialisten,” (The socialists of transition) he pledged allegiance to gradual reformist
change, which would be achieved by an increased awareness that the state does
not represent the interest of individuals.96
The first issue of Der individualistische Anarchist bears the date April 1,
1919. It appeared regularly in small book-format on the first and 16th of the month
until September 15. Its main contributors were Lachmann himself, who also used
the pen-name Antibarbarus. Other contributors included Friedrich Dobe, Hugo
Nansen, and Johanna Salzmann. It published mainly essays, but also fiction, poetry
and drama97 and engaged in something its mentor (Mackay) announced he was
not able to do, propaganda.
From this point of view, Der Einzige and Der individualistische Anarchist
complemented each other. While Der Einzige was mainly a theoretical project, Der
individualistische Anarchist focused on anarchist and individualist anarchist
literacy.98 Like Die Freiheit or Der Sozialist, both influential publications of the
Left, Der individualistische Anarchist included among its readers literate members
95
96
97
98
düsterer Ritter-Schmerz-Stimmung hinterlassen doch nicht selten ein Gefühl von Stürmen im
Glase Wasser, von wortreicher Ruhmredigkeit” (quoted in Fähnders 96).
The name of the journal already highlights Mackay’s influence.
“Ich habe Vertrauen zu einer allmählichen Entwicklung, in der sich Schritt für Schritt die
Autorität und Herrschaft des Staates verringert, weil die Menschen mehr und mehr erkennen
werden, dass ihr Interesse dort am besten aufgehoben ist, wo sie sich in freier Ausübung ihrer
Beschäftigung betätigen können.” Benedict Lachmann, “Die Übergangssozialisten,” 137.
It was one of the few radical political journals to publish women on a regular basis.
It also published, besides Stirner and Tucker pieces, texts by Kropotkin and Proudhon.
49
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
of the working class and artisans groups. It published economic analyses, and discussed concrete issues, such as elections, factory management, legislation, and
government reform. If Der Einzige was a provider of concepts and of examples of
intellectual revolt, Der individualistische Anarchist envisaged concrete institutional
and political changes.
Der individualistische Anarchist aimed more clearly at building a movement. The July 1 issue called on the revival of a “Vereinigung Individualistischer
Anarchisten.” Although Der Einzige had its own “Bund,” one would never read
in its pages a call like Lachmann’s:
Most of our friends believe that it is time to quit the mere theorizing and begin
to try to realize the principles of individualist anarchism.99
99
“Die meisten unserer Freunde sind der Ansicht, dass es Zeit ist mit dem bloßen Theoretisieren
aufzuhören und mit dem Versuche zu beginnen, die Prinzipien des individualistischen Anarchismus
zu realisieren.” Benedict Lachmann, “Aufruf,” 337.
50
CHAPTER 2
The Last Revolution
War and Revolution
From the very beginning Der Einzige’s voice was original within the leftist
camp. In the midst of intense revolutionary activity, it argued on the first page of
its first issue that revolutions could bring no authentic political change. Regardless
whether originating in the Left or the Right, the revolution, as imagined in 1919,
would lead to nothing more than the replacement of one repressive regime with
another. The true goal of a revolution was that of not having regimes at all. This
was the main argument of Anselm Ruest’s inaugural piece, “The Last Revolution.”
Revolutionary struggle had to be rethought. It should no longer be collective but
individual; it should no longer aim at creating a new order, but at abandoning
the idea of order as a whole.100
Der Einzige’s take on the war was also different from that of other progressive
journals of its time. For Der Einzige, the four-year bloodbath was neither an accident
in history nor the outcome of a certain form of government. The massacres of
World War I were the product of the state itself and state-based political European
and global order. It was only its abolition that could prevent such monstrous
massacres from ensuing again. As long as there was state, statist organization
and its practices of mobilization, like the ones in Germany in August 1914, war
was inevitable.101
100
101
Die letzte, größte, wahrhaftigste Revolution muss erst noch in Jedem, Jedem Einzigen sich
vollziehen, stattdessen drohen wir wieder auf halbem Wege stecken zu bleiben—darum: auf
der Hut vor jedem neuen Götzen, vor Knechtschaft und Versklavung. (1) All quotes are from
Der Einzige unless otherwise indicated.
In a letter from the frontlines (published in the third issue of Der Einzige and titled “Über den
völligen Bankerott jeder staatlichen Wirtschaft und Regierungskunst”) an army officer confessed
that it was the battlefield experience (and, I assume, the structures of obedience and the absurdity
of death) that convinced him that state organization was the source of war, and that after the
war one should think of alternative ways of organizing individuals in collectivities so that
this terrible event would never return (43).
51
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
When criticizing the return to statist structures which was happening in the
postwar period and the closure of history in eternalized political projects, Der
Einzige was referring to moments like August 1914, which gestured toward the
unlimited leverage of the state over its subjects and its ability to manipulate them.
From Der Einzige’s point of view, the revolution of 1918 failed because its outcome
was a return to statist organization. Revolutions would always fail because they
did not address the pre-rational (unconscious) dependency of men and women
on state structures. The state was constitutive to a subject’s self-understanding.
State structures did not give men and women the opportunity to envision themselves
and experiment with politics outside this framework.
The years 1918-1919 witnessed men and women desiring to escape the freedom
that they gained with the collapse of the imperial regime. This impulse to “escape
freedom,” later theorized by another German witness of the 1919 transformations,
Erich Fromm, made looking back at a moment like August 1914 so important.102
The patriotic delirium of those days might provide one with answers regarding
the way in which state structures operated upon the subject and alienated men
and women from their ownness. 1914 also could provide some answers as to
how to counter these predatory practices of the state.
The power void of 1918-1919 showed the twentieth-century human in a new
light. This human was no longer the self-governing individual envisioned by the
liberal state. The power void brought to the fore a disoriented being, one frightened
by freedom and addicted to transcendent guidance. Stirner’s predictions proved
to be true: liberalism had failed to produce a free subject; instead it created a
monad that conceived of itself as incomplete, as part of something bigger than
him or her: an order, a body politic or a mission. This explains why, in 1919, after
the bigger entity, the nation, of which the individual Ichs were a part of, collapsed,
its “elements” rushed into rebuilding it, its hierarchies and teleologies. The
passion of “rebuilding” the future—Germany, the republic, the nation, etc.—was
in fact a rejection of the true opportunities of 1919. This rejection was caused
by the desire to forget and return, symbolically, to a moment prior to the fall of
the regime, to a moment of integration and being in common.
Der Einzige’s commitment to oppose such practices of integration can be
found in the self-description of the journal or in the article by Ruest I referred
102
Erich Fromm, Escape from Freedom. New York: Farrar and Rinehart, 1941.
52
2. The Last Revolution
to, suggestively titled “The Last Revolution.” In its self-descriptive blurb, Der
Einzige introduces itself as an individualist (anarchist) journal that is not affiliated
with any party (which of course did not mean it was not political). It presents
itself as fighting mass-suggestion and mass-psychosis. Its mission is “an appeal
to the singularity,” to the singular being, whose affirmation (revolt) is the key
political practice of breaking the ideological spell that arrests radical democratic
social networks. Der Einzige defined the present times as in turmoil (“verwirrte
Gegenwart”), and considered as “Mit-Arbeiter” every soul interested in candidly
asserting their disobedience and reliance on themselves (“ehrlichen Zu-sichselbst-Bekenntis akklamieren”), and which, “after five years of mass delusion,
have kept their senses and mind intact, have not discarded reasoning.”103
August 1914
One way of understanding the catastrophe of August of 1914 is through the
number of casualties it generated. World War I killed ten million people and
wounded and crippled many more. Another ten million died of disease and hunger.
Another way of reading the war, Der Einzige argued, was as a triumph of the
state over the individual, of organization and mobilization over autonomy. The
state had successfully persuaded its subjects to sacrifice their most precious asset,
their own lives.
This “success” could not be evaluated by means of a body count. It rested
in the conformism and the lack of dissent with which state and war propaganda
were accepted by the population.104 The nationalist delirium of August 1914
constituted a chilling moment for the German intellectual community and the
German Left. As if spellbound, German intellectuals abandoned independent
thinking. They fell prey to the sweeping enthusiasm of identification with the
103
104
“… nach fünf Jahren der Massenverblendung seine Sinne noch unversehrt, seinen Verstand—
als solchen—behalten, seine Vernunft nicht weggeworfen hat” (12).
The Grand Mobilization of 1914 demonstrated how dangerously effective the state and its
ideological apparatuses had become in manipulating its subjects. Testimonies from enthusiasts
of the day speak for this widespread Massensuggestion. Here is one such profession of
“Entselbstung” from philosopher Alois Riehl: “Never was a people so united as in those August
days, those unforgettable days. A higher life seemed to reveal itself to us. Each of us felt, each
of us lived for the whole, and the whole lived in us all. Our more narrow self with its personal
interests merged into the great historical self of the nation.” Quoted in Wolfgang Kruse, “The
First World War,” 70.
53
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
nation. On the political front, 1914 marked the betrayal by German social democracy
of the pacifist international socialism and its call on Germany’s workers to die
for the interests of their exploiters.
For individualist anarchists, the war confirmed Stirner’s theories regarding
the pernicious nature of the state. Their postwar task was thus to continue unraveling the structural violence inherent in the design of state structures and its
technologies of producing obedient subjects whose warped desires made them
freely and willingly embrace a miserable death on the frontline and participate
enthusiastically in the appalling act of killing other human beings. Individualist
anarchists would focus on what one of the young contributors to Der Einzige,
Erich Barth, called “die Epidemie” of obedience that had struck Germany in the
twentieth century (181-183).
August 1914 was revolutionary because it aimed at recasting the ultimate
goal of the political and changing the course the French Revolution gave history.
The German Volk was to redeem humankind and replace the degenerate ideal of
freedom that had been invented in 1789. The new keyword, intellectuals like
Rudolf Kjellén and Johann Plenge argued, was “order.”105 The age of Western
liberalism, individualism, international agreements, and human rights was over
for these ideologues. Humanity had entered a new stage of development: organization at a national level. The meaning of being individual per se was nil. It
could gain meaning only in relationship to a collectivity. The values of this new
era were: “Devotion, faith, integration, heroism; in short, the superindividual,
[and] the tested in hardship will to sacrifice.”106 As outcome of individual will,
freedom made no sense, another ideologue of 1914, Adolf von Harnack argued.
Freedom was vigorously doing one’s duty for the nation.107
105
106
107
“Ordnung ist das große Wort …, das bedeutet organische Struktur, Hierarchie, Rang-Ordnung.”
Quoted in Kurt Flasch, Die geistige Mobilmachung, 280. Kruse highlights the enthusiasm with
which the word was used in the immediate pre-war context. According to Theodor Heuss, the
term was used only with exclamation marks. “The German secret” was the nation’s ability to
organize itself, and this organization was possible due to the heroic mentality of its citizens:
“the preparedness to fit oneself into society and […] in the allegedly efficient structure of the
bureaucratic authoritarian state” (78). Even among the leaders of the SPD, there were voices
stating that “the age of individualism is coming to an end” (Paul Lensch quoted in Kruse 79).
“Hingabe, Glaube, Einordnung, Heldentum, kurz das Überindividuelle, [das] in Härte erprobte
Opfer fordernde.” Kurt Flasch, Die geistige Mobilmachung, 282.
Reinhard Rürup, “Die Ideologisierung des Krieges,” 137.
54
2. The Last Revolution
Revolution
When attacking the Spartacist uprising in “The Last Revolution,” Ruest was
bearing in mind the August 1914 war-mobilizing revolution and its monstrous
consequences. Even if a Bolshevik revolution and a nationalist conservative one
emerged from radically different platforms, their means did not seem so different.
Both mobilized, asserted a religion of the future, manipulated masses, and aimed
at building a new state structure. For Ruest, if another revolution was to take
place, its practices had to change. It should be a “revolution of singularities,”
oriented not against one form of government, but against the idea of government
and citizenship altogether.
These ideas were not original, and Ruest did not pretend they were. His article
started with a long quote from Stirner. Ruest was continuing Stirner’s critique
of the religious mind and was adapting the latter’s ideas to the postwar context.108
In 1914, the state was cherished as a new god, and Stirner’s ideas denounced
nationalism, proclaimed the death of the German Volk, and called for the affirmation of the singularity of the self. Ruest also showed that this critique of
nationalism and the state was not made in the name of liberal democracy (the
discourse of the Entente) or in the name of pacifist humanism (á la Romain
Rolland109 and Stefan Zweig).110 If World War I was a clash of Weltanschauungen,
as war enthusiasts like Thomas Mann argued,111 Der Einzige supported neither.
It called for the death of the state and of its main ideological product, humanist
discourse and the duties of being human it laid out. Not only nations had to be
108
109
110
111
I should add Nietzsche’s name here as the other formidable critic of religious thinking. However,
since the Entente war propaganda machine vilified Nietzsche as the philosopher of war, his
presence on the front page might have needed some preparation. It is obvious that Der
Einzige wanted to free Nietzsche’s name from its pro-war, nationalist, irrationalist, and antiindividualist labeling. They did it, however, with caution.
Though in a future issue, Der Einzige would publish a pacifist article by Rolland’s “guru,”
Mahatma Gandhi.
To undo the working of the mobilizing war machine, Ruest argued in his article “—aber lügt
nicht zu sehr...”, singularities had to detour mobilizing abstractions used by this machine, as
well as not fall into the traps of a sentimental pacifism, centered on an discourse of love,
which is just another form of humanism idyllically reconstructing the human as a peaceful
animal. The same was true with regard to mobilizing postwar socialism or other forms of statist
organization like liberal democracy (50-51).
In his famous Betrachtungen eines Unpolitischen, Mann speaks about the conflict between
German “Kultur” and its arch-enemy, Western “Zivilisation.”
55
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
abolished, but also a certain collectivist understanding of being human. So far,
no system had sincerely supported the autonomy of the sovereign singularity.
The key strategy to fight state organization and the universal brainwashing was
by resisting humanist discourse and by affirming the singularity schizophrenically
and non-dialectically. The Volk is dead, proclaimed Ruest. Long live the Ich.
Humanity is on its way to the grave, he went on and my Ich “is their laughing heir”
(1). Mensch and Menschheit were the abstract principles on which the state was
organized. The violence inherent in these concepts needed to be unraveled critically
(dialectically). This act of unraveling needed also to target the disciplining nature
of conceptual language and the idiom built around the “human,” as well as the
humanist political imaginary. The identity produced by rituals and concepts needed
to be exploded. On the affirmative (non-dialectical) side, the disciplining identity
that these concepts induced had to be ignored and overcome by creation.112 But
again, Ruest’s article stressed, not in a collective way. Not by building yet another
machine of order. But differently, without mobilization, without teleology.
One notices that an article like “The Last Revolution” addressed a multitude
of issues. As such its very form enacted the generalized rebellion. It was not focused
only on one topic, though one could discern that the critique of the idea of a final
political cause was given a certain centrality. If revolts should not have a cause
that was carved in stone, this should apply to texts and programmatic texts as well.
Ruest’s writings cultivated serendipity and improvisation. Like revolt itself, writing
was supposed to lack an obvious direction. It should also be tormented by passion.
This “passion” that made a text unpredictable at the level of content, vocabulary
and even in syntax was fueled by Nietzschean affirmation. It constituted the eruption
of singularity on the written page and the assertion of the eventual nature of the
text (text as event), which became more than a mediation between two rituals of
signification.
Returning to the critique of revolution, Ruest’s logic was the following: since
there was no such thing as the human, mobilization was alienating in the sense
that it was forcing the singularity into a form of human. Mobilization was for
something, and that something was built on an essentialized multiple (vs. the
singular). Once this essentializing device called Mensch was abandoned, and
112
Here the concept of creative forgetting, forgetting by and through creation inspired by Nietzsche is
essential.
56
2. The Last Revolution
singularity acknowledged, the “for something” of mobilization became relativized
to each autonomous I, and no universal and enslaving telos could be proclaimed.113
Ruest emphasized that Der Einzige’s politics were to reverse the “achievements”
of a revolution such as that of August 1914, and the organizing that it produced.114
Instead of taking pains in building a “we” (the main task of a manifesto), Ruest’s
piece called on its readers to “dis-identify” and distance themselves from collective
causes and to practice belonging to themselves (3). The article addressed its
readers with the pronoun you (Du) and called on them to rebel, to listen only to
their individual voice, ignore the ethical and patriotic imperatives and the perverse
definitions of freedom and life worth living that emerged from the delirium of
war propaganda and that returned to the present of 1919. If August 1914 was
about overcoming individualism and the burden of being oneself and with
oneself, Der Einzige’s 1919 position was exactly the opposite, that is, fighting
the burden of being arrested, as Mensch, into a structure. If a philosopher like Max
Scheler described August 1914 as a moment of communal ecstasy, in which, finally,
“we were no longer what we were for such a long time: alone, with a ruptured
contact between all levels of life. Individual – people – nation – world – God
113
114
Ruest’s position, expressed while the Spartacist rebellion was unfolding, was also consistent
with that of most anarchists of his time. In his Memoirs, Rudolf Rocker synthesized the postrevolutionary realities of Weimar Germany. Rocker was as skeptical as Ruest regarding the
agents of change of the early post-war days. For him, there was no difference between the SPD
and the USPD. Both were Marxist and centralist, and the differences between them were
related only to the way in which they wanted to seize power. Der Einzige’s sibling journal,
Der individualistische Anarchist, also published pieces incriminating the Räte-style uprisings
of 1918 and 1919, and brought to the fore the similarities between 1914 and 1918. For
Friedrich Partmuß, the “revolutions” of 1914 and 1918 were the same because their heroes
“suchten den Weg zu einem Ideal […] Die Militaerpartei von 1919: der Spartakusbund, steht
nicht höher, als die Kreigbegeisterten von 1914. [...]. In 1914 handelte es sich um das Reich,
heute um eine Klasse, oder viel mehr: man sagt, es handele sich darum” (“Zur Zeit,” 180).
In opposing the spirit of 1914, Der Einzige also anticipates the moment of 1933, when again
the same mobilization of society takes place. Rurüp highlights that many of the values of
1914 will be reused in 1933. “‘Volksgemeinschaft’ gegen ‘Klassengemeinschaft,’ ‘nationaler
Sozialismus’ gegen ‘Staatssozialismus,’ ‘Organisation’ als Grundprinzip der sozialen Beziehungen
gegen Individualismus und liberale Freiheitsrechte, ‘deutsche Kultur’ gegen ‘westliche Zivilisation,’
‘Weltmacht’ und ‘nationaler Egoismus’ – das alles waren Wert- und Zielvorstellungen, an die
der Nationalsozialismus in seinem Kampf gegen die Weimarer Republik anknüpfen konnte.
Der ‘Geist von 1914’ bot ein reichhaltiges Arsenal ideologischer Waffen, aus dem die Nationalsozialisten sich erfolgreich zu bedienen wussten” (Rurüp Ideologisierung 141).
57
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
were suddenly reconnected,”115 Ruest would value these sufferings as the virtues
of the rebel.
The underlying argument for this contrast comes again from Stirner. One of
the young contributors to Der Einzige, Paul Gurk, synthesized it: “You are all parts,
tools, and service each other. Neither is whole and serves him- or herself.”116
The “sufferings” Scheler mentioned were state induced. They were the effect of
the statist production of subjectivity as dependent on a higher structure such as
the Church, the Party or the State. The invention of Mensch, Stirner had argued,
rested on the humiliation and enslavement of the singularity.117 The state perpetuated itself by using a network of dependencies. The state had perverted the
priorities of the Enlightenment. Education, morals, religion and civilization were
instrumental not only in generating intellectual emancipation, but also subjection.
The invention of the human soul, emotions, traditions, and ends constituted the
main tools the state employed in keeping men and women enslaved. They were
more effective than its prisons, its madhouses, its army, and its police. Humanism,
the religion of the state, injected the subject with the desire to fill a lack. This was
statist humiliation. The subject was the effect of this narrative of incompleteness.
It was interpellated as incomplete and coerced into identifying with something
imposed upon it discursively—an ideal, a spook.118
115
116
117
118
“Wir waren nicht mehr, was wir so lange waren: Allein! Der Zerrissene Lebenskontakt zwischen
den Reihen: Individuum – Volk – Nation – Welt – Gott wurde mit einem Male wieder geschlossen.”
Quoted in Reinhard, Rürup, “Die Ideologisierung des Krieges,” 125.
“Ihr alle seid Teile, Werkzeuge und dient einander. Keiner ist ganz und dient sich selbst” (180).
This is the basic assumption of the state theories of Hobbes, Rousseau and Hegel. Hobbes
legitimizes the invention of a state on the assumption that man is morally flawed. In a state of
nature, humans live miserably. They need institutions to mediate their living in common.
Rousseau employs a more positive strategy. Man is not evil, only imperfect. Since, however,
humans strive for improvement, they need a state because they want to overcome their natural
situation of “stupid and unimaginative animals” (28). For Hegel, it is only the state that can
give meaning to the individual’s life. In The Rebel, Camus highlights that Hegel’s philosophy
makes man so dependent on the state that it lays the very essence of being human in the
hands of his or her co-citizens. Self-consciousness is the product of my relationship to others.
Stirner’s critique starts from the following hypothesis: “Wir sind in jedem Augenblick alles
was wir sein können, und brauchen niemals mehr zu sein. Da kein Mangel auf uns haftet, so
hat auch die Sünde keinen Sinn” (Der Einzige und sein Eigentum, 404).
In Der Einzige und sein Eigentum, Stirner highlights the various masks of the state. It is a
father figure from which the minor child always has to ask for allowance (118-119). It
interpellates its subjects as eternal criminals in order to reinforce their moral inferiority:
“Jedes Ich ist von Geburt schon ein Verbrecher gegen das Volk, den Staat” (119). It is the
doctor that takes care of its patients (220-221). It is that holy institution which makes sure
that every self-interested deed is denounced as a profanity (224): “Der Staat hat immer nur
58
2. The Last Revolution
Mobilization
The experience of the nineteenth-century modern liberal state reveals that state
organization and mobilization are overlapping concepts. A secular state, whose
transcendence is history, maintains its structures by mobilizing the minds and
hands of its subjects for the making of a better future. I discriminate between the
two concepts here, because I address a time period of intense “revolutionary”
activity that called for radical breaks with the past, imagined moments of intense
historical acceleration (mobilization) and opposed them to periods of historical
calm (organization). The reality behind these so-called “decisive moments in
history”119 is that the nineteenth-century state had not only intertwined mobilization
and organization in its technologies of subject production, but had incorporated
other “revolutions” (like the industrial revolution) into its everyday practices of
organization. The state that had moved away from a celestial anchorage had
recast its religious thinking upon history. It often survived by declaring states
of emergency to cover up its lack of organization and to stimulate and accelerate
it—integrating its mobilization strategies within its technologies of selfperpetuation.
This position against the 1914 and 1919 revolutions was reiterated by Ruest
in the second issue of the journal. In an editorial titled “Where Are the Intellectuals?”
(Wo sind die Geistigen?) he renewed the attack on the socialist camp. He denounced
socialist socialization as metaphysics, as a unio mystica, in the way Stirner denounced humanism. Looking back at the “trahison des clercs” of 1914,120 and at
the instrumental role intellectuals had played in the mobilizing process, Ruest
asked rhetorically who needed again these mobilizers posturing as mouthpieces
of the people in 1919. Who needed their lyrical exhortations and their disciplining discourses? Who needed them to invent common causes and lead nations
towards something that was not in the true interest of the singularities that built
these nations?
119
120
den Zweck den Einzelnen zu beschränken, zu bändigen, zu subordinieren, ihn irgend einem
Allgemeinen Untertan zu machen” (249).
As theorized in 1927 by Stefan Zweig in his eponymous classic Sternstunden der Menschheit.
As presented in the 1927 eponymous classic by Julien Benda. The Betrayal of the Intellectuals
refers to European thinkers who abandoned independent critical thinking in favor of supporting
state power.
59
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
The attack on the socialist camp was probably influenced by the bad news
coming from the Soviet Union. Another revolution was turning into a repressive dictatorship of party bureaucrats. In “On Communism and Anarchy” (Zu
Kommunismus und Anarchie) and under the pseudonym Panarchos, Raoul
Hausmann criticized Marxist communism in the spirit of the 1891 split of the
German Left. Communism was again just another statist discourse that had
turned men and women into obedient executors of a political master plan. The
evil of party organization and revolutionary mobilization, the article highlighted,
rested on the insulting interpellation of the ordinary human as nothing more than
an instrument for the fulfillment of the grand project of building a “better world.”
Statist communism corrupted the human beings’ relationship to themselves (56),
life’s dynamics, its creativity, “the expansion of one’s own experience; the full
development of one’s will, one’s self and other; one’s balance above the abyss
of death, violence and theft; as well the dissolution of one’s borders” (56).121
Seeking collective emancipation through collectivist ethics and law alienated
men and women from defining their own law. By essentializing the concept of
work, Marxist communism identified the human with his or her social role.
Responding to the realities in the Soviet Union, the article warned that the
singularity would always return and ask for what was its own. Sympathizing
with revolutionary anarchism, Hausmann did not argue that what had been started
in the Soviet Union should be dropped. Unlike Ruest (and closer to Marxism),
he hoped that, eventually, the phase of the dictatorship of the proletariat would
be overcome, the revolutionary avant-garde would self-dissolve, decentralized
soviets would rule, and the Soviet Union would not become just another centralized
state. Revolution’s role (even if engineered by an avant-garde) was to break up
the state and disentangle individuals from the network of social control. Its final
goal was anarchy. The nation would dissolve into singularities who would then
create, ex nihilo, social life. The anarchy produced by revolution had thus the
role of creating a context of self-discovery and of regaining individual sovereignty
(in Stirner’s terms: sich eignen). This experience of anarchy constituted the basis
of an ethical regeneration that would bestow egos with a mature (responsible
and un-naive) political conduct and would offer them the means to understand
121
“Die Ausarbeitung des eigenen Erlebens, die volle Entfaltung eines Willens, sein Ich und Du,
seine Ballance über dem Abgrund des Todes, der Gewalt und des Diebstahls, die Auflösung
seiner Grenzen.”
60
2. The Last Revolution
the compromise society constituted. They would autonomously administer the
power given to them by anarchy and start the war of all against all understood
affirmatively,122 that is, the true building of the self without institutional mediation
and self-alienation in social roles.
Individual Revolt
Ruest’s position was not similar to Hausmann’s, in spite of their common
Stirnerian background.123 Ruest did not believe in a revolutionary avant-garde—
not even a self-dissolving one. He rejected the idea that a violent collective campaign
would allow egos to take themselves into possession. He also expressed skepticism
regarding the enlightening effects of such a campaign, in particular regarding
its possibility to allow egos to re-learn political action and practice it. The war
experience and the events of 1918-1919 showed that after a violent event and
an implosion of power, individuals, now allegedly in a state of nature, did not
experience the radical democratic illumination that would awaken in them a
drive to co-exist in a qualitatively superior form of community. Rather, post-event
subjects and collectivities acted as agents in what seemed the universal process
of the return of the same. If revolution for Hausmann seemed to look like an outburst
that would trigger an immediate and reliable spontaneous organization of the
masses (as Rosa Luxemburg, the theoretician of the Spartacist League envisioned),
for Ruest and other collaborators of Der Einzige (Friedlaender included) it would
look, as I already suggested, more like an epidemic, like the proliferation of an
infection over a longer period of time. The germ spreading from one individual
to another was disobedience, Frechheit, individual revolt—what Stirner called
Empörung.
Since revolution needed to be abandoned together with the ideas of common
cause and mobilizing elite, individual revolt became the mechanism allowing
egos to achieve autonomy and thus develop singular goals. “Ich muss mich
empören, um emporzukommen,” Stirner argued in a quote reproduced by Der
122
123
This is different from Hobbes’ imagining of the war of all against all. Hobbes’ pessimism is
influenced by the fear of civil war.
Only a few weeks after publishing this article, Hausmann would distance himself from Der
Einzige’s politics and even write pamphlets against it. I will return to Hausmann’s position in
Chapter 4, where I discuss Der Einzige’s relationship to the Dada movement.
61
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
Einzige under title “On Freedom and Revolution” (Über Freiheit und Revolution)
(56). It meant that one needed to revolt in order to break through. For him,
Empörung did not constitute a struggle against a certain political system, something
that revolutions were after, but only the action of working out one’s own from
“what is” the current predicament (das Bestehende) (354).124 He meant disengagement from the organizing and mobilizing networks of the modern state.
For individualist anarchists, Stirner’s antihumanist position emphasized that
central to this “what is” was the idea of the human itself and the way in which
subjectivity was constructed within the organizational and statist framework.
As the title of the piece emphasizes, Stirner’s critique of the idea of revolution
was integrated in the opposition between the concepts of freedom (Freiheit) and
individual sovereignty or autonomy (Eigentum). Freedom was the goal of revolutions. It was negative freedom, freedom from. It assumed that there were specific
rights that had to be won by means of violence or radical transformation. It
assumed the existence of an entity bestowed with the legitimacy to grant these
rights. An essentialist understanding of the I derived from here. Revolutions
aimed at liberating this entity immobilized in a false identity by apparatuses of
discipline and restoring its authenticity via its rights.
Individualist anarchist critique of revolution stressed that freedom and revolution were unsustainable approaches to change because they called on singularities
to fight for something that they already had, autonomy. The error of revolutionary
collectivist thinking was that it posited freedom before autonomy, and that it
valued an abstraction—the socially and politically defined subject—more than
the reality of the concrete singularity, its Eigenheit. In the words of Der Einzige
und sein Eigentum, freedom functioned as longing for something and awakened
the wrath against that which one did not have. On the contrary, the practice of
egotism called on celebrating oneself and as such eliminating unfreedom in the
present. I am sovereign, Stirner argues, already when I say it! Revolt has no future,
no transcendence, and no grand battle to prepare for. It is just disobedience
practiced at every moment of one’s everyday life.125
124
125
“Nur ein Herausarbeiten Meiner aus dem Bestehenden.”
Die ”Freiheit” weckt euren Grimm gegen Alles was ihr nicht seid; der “Egoismus” ruft Euch
zur Freude über Euch selbst, zum Selbstgenusse; die “Freiheit” ist und bleibet eine Sehnsucht,
ein romantischer Klagelaut, eine christliche Hoffnung auf Jenseitigkeit und Zukunft; die
62
2. The Last Revolution
Inspired by Stirner, Friedlaender/ Mynona wrote a “presentist” manifesto in
Der Sturm. It was the manifesto of his antihumanist revolt.126 According to Dieter
Lehner, this essay had a significant impact on the bohemia and on the avantgarde circles. As the title already suggested, the article argued against the idea
of revolution and the transcendence that it presupposed. Under the rubric “my
strategy of rebelling,” it advocated the practice of rendering oneself indifferent
in the spirit of the early Romantics. Indifference, creative indifference, was
Friedlaender/ Mynona’s translation of Stirnerian disobedience. Being indifferent
meant neither disregard for the other nor an idealist utopia of insulation “from
the outside.” Singularity was understood discursively, and indifference referred
to a practice of actively balancing the binary oppositions that constructed the
singularity and its “Eigentum.” “I am a royal nothing,” Friedlaender/ Mynona wrote.
This meant not a negative zero, but a neutral, medial, in-different absence on the
basis of which the I could dance “within the chaos of all negations and positions.”127
Younger contributors like Gerhard Lehmann criticized revolution employing
the concept of obedience (Gehorsamkeit). Gehorsamkeit was Hörigkeit (bondage)
subordination to an idea (64).128 It was the state of a mind possessed by the
spooks of an abstraction. The revolutionary mind could not be autonomous; it
just perpetuated structures of subjection. In order to gain autonomy the idea
needed to be permanently renewed.129 This renewal could be granted only by a
generalized practice of disobedience that would become instrumental in the
126
127
128
129
“Eigenheit” ist eine Wirklichkeit, die von selbst gerade so viel Unfreiheit beseitigt, als Euch
hinderlich den eigenen Weg versperrt. Max Stirner, Der Einzige und sein Eigentum, 180.
“Ich bin präsent. Menschen waren oder warden.” S. Friedlaender, “Präsentismus,” 253.
“Ich bin das kaiserliche Nichts: nicht die negative Null, sondern die neutrale, mediale,
indifferent, die ich personifizierte und mit der ich wie als Stein im Chaos aller Negationen
und Positionen tanzen kann.” Dr. S. Friedlaender, “Präsentismus,” 253. I will offer a detailed
analysis of Friedlaender/ Mynona’s reading of Stirner and of his concept of indifference in
Chapter 4.
“Gehorsamkeit ist Hörigkeit und Unterordnung unter eine Idee! […] Wenn es noch irgend
einen Gedanken gibt, den ich seit der Kindheit übernommen habe ohne ihn zu prüfen, wenn
es noch irgend einen Gedanken gibt das Macht über mich hat, so ist das Gehorsam—Gehorsam
im Glauben (64).” Gehorsamkeit engendered organized communities. Opposed to both reform
and revolution, Der Einzige aimed at building a certain culture of civil restlessness that
would render mobilizing machines dysfunctional. As Michel Foucault argued in the History
of Sexuality, “the agency of domination does not reside in the one who speaks (for it is he
who is constrained), but in the one who listens and says nothing; not in the one who knows
and answers, but in the one who questions and is not supposed to know” (62).
“Unser Zukunftsideal—wenn das Wort nicht zu schmierig klingt—unser Zukunftsideal ist
derart, dass es sich stündlich realisiert” (64).
63
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
dismantling of organizations. The practice of revolt was this bold self-affirmation,
and the repercussions of this practice within the realm of the political were the
rendering dysfunctional and spontaneous of the body politic.
The centrality of the concept of suggestion for Der Einzige’s political analysis
reveals that it adopted Stirner and Nietzsche’s reading of the state as a structure
similar in constitution and practices to the Church. If differences between these
two institutions existed, they were limited to their disciplining spectacle. In God
and the State, Bakunin argued that “There is not, there cannot be, a State without
religion,” that is, without religious forms of understanding political life (84). 130
The theoreticians of the modern state themselves highlighted this symbiosis. In
his Social Contract, J.J. Rousseau emphasized that the structures of the state
could not stand together without the neo-pagan cult of the state (40). Although
Rousseau opposed Christianity and referred to it as a religion of servitude, he
called for the state to invent a religion for itself, a “profession of faith which is
purely civil […] without which it is impossible to be a good citizen or a loyal
subject” (186).131 This religion administered the desire of the subject, incited
the flame of identification with the nation and helped to grant spectacular reality
to the abstract idea of the common interest. It was this desire/ flame/ Rausch,
this opium that “suggested” (as Der Einzige put it) the self-understanding of the
singularity as citizen, that transformed the community into the unio mystica within
the body of the nation.
Here is how important religious thinking was for theoreticians of the state
like Rousseau:
If anyone, after having publicly acknowledged these same dogmas [of state
religion], behaves as if he did not believe in them, then let him be put to death,
for he has committed the greatest crime, that of lying before the law.132
For individualist anarchists the act of disobeying, of breaking this spell of
“suggestion” was the revolutionary act itself. There was no need for another
transcendence, for another definition of the meaning of life, for another religion
130
131
132
For Bakunin, Protestantism was the state religion par excellence, especially in its deist forms.
Deism embodied the symbiosis of reason and faith, making one work for the other as a
unitary whole in the service of the state.
For Rousseau, this religion meant putting forward “dogmas” that were “simple and few in
number, expressed precisely and without explanations or commentaries,” for people to believe
in (186).
J.J. Rousseau, The Social Contract, 186.
64
2. The Last Revolution
to legitimate it, and for another promise placed in the future. There was no need
for another mass mobilization. Revolt was the antonym for religion. Der Einzige’s
intervention and its prospects for change centered on what Jean-Luc Nancy’s
The Inoperative Community called the permanent interruption of the myth of
the state.133 The goal of interruption—Stirner’s Emporkommen, Friedlaender/
Mynona’s living in the present or Lehmann’s Ungehorsamkeit regarding one’s
own subjective construction—was to make these communities un-mobilizable.
The war-experience highlighted the destructive character of essential communities.
Because they were created on essences and sameness, states and revolutions
invented a radical other that was unsubsumable to the essence. This radical other
became the enemy, be it that of the class struggle or of the other as nation, and
this led to wars, Ruest argued in his article “Attila the Plague of God” (Attila
die Gottesgeißel) (36-38).
Antihumanism
It was with calls for humanism, morality and culture, that the state mobilized
against this Other. In another article, titled “… but Don’t Lie Too Much!” (—aber
lügt nur nicht zu sehr!), Ruest expressed his outrage with the many definitions
of justice, humanity, culture and peoples’ and human rights that the press was
generating, regarding this intense verbal output as a conspicuous form of violence
in times of peace.134 Essences, Paul Gurk argued in “The Drive to Kill” (Der Trieb
zu töten) (296-8), triggered a permanent state of war of the singularity with itself.
He analyzes the way in which mortifying oneself and others in the name of ideals
brought war to the core of human civilization. War was another grand mobilizing
machine. It was thus no surprise that the American radical writer Randolph Bourne
coined the phrase “War is the health of the state” during this period. The modern
133
134
Nancy’s The Inoperative Community is a project similar to Der Einzige. It is an effort to define
a community that is not one of humans or individuals, but one of singularities. It advocates a
practice of revolt that consists in the affirmation of these singularities (their “passion for
being”) against their essentializing as humans.
“... zu keiner Zeit des Friedens war je von ewiger Gerechtigkeit, von Menschentum und
Bestimmung, von Humanität und ungeschriebenen Gesetzen, von Kultur und Völkerrecht und
siegreichen Ideen so geschwätzig die Rede. Seit wann hatte Macht und brutale Gewalt so viele
Worte gemacht?” (50).
65
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
state was in a permanent state of war because it needed to reinforce the rule of
the ideal.135
Individualist anarchism is not another ideology, but a hybrid assemblage of
un-pious “ideologies” coming from singularities, whose important duty, Stirner
argues, is to remain disobedient including toward anarchism itself (and not turn
it into a religion).136 This was possible, Der Einzige argued, if all these ideologies
were not predicated upon the collective subject with a telos. Among singularities
that did not share humanity, everyone was an other. Within this predicament,
assimilation to sameness became inconceivable. Interruption of myth, Nancy
highlights, is not a myth itself. Nancy emphasizes that interruption is only a
“trembling at the age of being,” and not a code of conduct.
For Der Einzige, the assertion of the Nichts, as the absence on which the I
was built, was the guarantee that another mythology did not come into being.
Nancy argues that a “myth of the absence of myth” is not a myth in the totalitarian
sense because its narrative is not only undermined by the absence at its core, but
also because it only produces a closure of history as opening. It “is itself neither
another myth, nor a negative myth (nor the negative of a myth), but it is a myth
only inasmuch as it consists in the interruption of myth.”137
Interruption is performed in a singular voice, and it takes place, as Friedlaender/
Mynona stressed, only in the present. It rejects the future and transcendence. It
is not the voice of a we speaking in the name of a we and for a we. It is the
Einzige (the singularity) asserting itself as its Eigentum (sovereignty, ownness),
which stands as the basis of an ethics and politics of the singularity. It “presents
[in Nancy’s words] the mythless truth of endless being-in-common, of this being
in common that is not ‘common being.’” The community itself cannot control it
and it is incapable of founding or containing.138
Lehmann believed that disobedience triggered the “Lockerung” of the state
structure. It produced a state of dysfunction that spread gradually, like an epidemic,
throughout the entire mechanism of generating collective servitude. Revolt, unlike
revolution, did not proclaim that there was something like an outside agency
that could intervene and change the structure. Everything happened from inside,
135
136
137
138
See Howard Zinn, A People’s History of the United States, 359.
Saul Newman, Max Stirner, 183.
Jean-Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community, 61.
Jean-Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community, 62.
66
2. The Last Revolution
monistically, rejecting any transcendent locus, other than the singularity, its
continuous becoming and its trace of interruption, which would serve as the
anchorage of change.
Because it refused constructing an Other as enemy, or a conflict between
multiples, revolt spoke the idiom of what Deleuze and Guattari call a minor language. Minor language opposes the idea of dialect, which accepts transcendence,
and is the language of revolution. Dialect and minor language are both “deviances”
from the major and normative idiom. Minor language, however, thrives within
the major idiom and does not try to center itself in an irreconcilable difference.
The dialect essentializes this difference and aims at separating (dividing) and at
producing an autonomous multitude.
Minor practices are subversive, and they seek neither to establish boundaries
nor to become hegemonic in an appropriated territory. They do not impose order
and oppose with the aim of replacing. No revolution, no turnover of a certain order
is desired. Separations and essential oppositions are prerequisites to exclusions
and conflicts. Minor practices are rebellions unfolding within what the contemporary
individualist anarchist philosopher Hakim Bey calls the “the fractal dimensions
invisible to the cartography of Control,”139 whereas dialects aim at constructing
a new topology.
By imagining change as the effect of practices of Lösen und Lockern, Lehman
advocated such a minor approach. His argument was that one cannot defeat a
closed movement by countering it with another essence, but only by “letting the
inertia of this movement dissolve and loosen, only by injecting self-consciousness
and strength into individuals.”140 The Stirnerian Empörung was the practice that
produced this dissolving and loosening (lösen und lockern). Der Einzige imagined
itself as a site of such revolts aiming at this loosening of the “what is,” the
predicament (das Bestehende). Lockern created space for self-organization, selfknowledge, and self-affirmation. It was a reaffirmation of Eduard Bernstein’s
famous saying that “the movement is everything: the goal nothing” (die Bewegung
ist alles, das Ziel ist nichts) which the statist socialist movement had misinterpreted.
And because it was aimless revolt, pure assertion of what I am and what I want
139
140
Hakim Bey, TAZ, 103.
“Man kann eine geschlossene Bewegung nicht dadurch besiegen, dass man ihr eine Einheit
entgegensetzt, sondern nur dadurch, dass man die Inheit dieser Bewegung sich lösen und lockern
lässt, nur dadurch, dass man den Individuen Selbstbewusstsein und Stärke einflösst” (65).
67
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
without a program, Empörung questioned the necessity of revolutionary institutions. Change would be produced by the restless agitation of the undocile and
uncontainable body of the self-controlled singularity. If something would break
organization apart, it would not be the workers with weapons in their hands.
They were the agents of the eternal return. Change was more likely to come from
the provoking demeanor of the bohemian, the unruly rambling of the outcast,
and the outrageous attitude of the egotist.
All anarchist critiques of the state promoted de-centralized, federalist or, as
Deleuze and Guattari put it, rhizomatic forms of organization. Regardless if they
were nineteenth-century Kropotkinists or philosophers of difference of the post1968 era like Nancy, they argued in favor of a polity that, “in contrast to centered
(even polycentric) systems with hierarchical modes of communication and preestablished paths,” were “a-centered, nonhierarchical, nonsignifying […] without
a General and without an organizing memory or a central automaton, defined
solely by a circulation of states.”141 It was a form of life-sharing that had no
history, no principles, no objectives, and for which questions like “Where are you
going? Where are you coming from? What are you heading for?” were “totally
useless questions.”142
What made Stirner and Der Einzige’s critique of the state unique within the
anarchist spectrum was their antihumanism. Humanism turned the subject into
a means. Stirner’s logic was not far from that of Aristotle who argued that the
slave was that human being with whom somebody (or something) else could do
something, who “does not belong to itself,” who was a “piece of property” that is
“meant for action,” meant to serve a purpose that transcends his or her interests.143
141
142
143
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, 25.
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, 25.
Aristotle, Politics, 59. Nietzsche reasserts Stirner’s antihumanism in his critique of the state.
The state, like religion before, is the new moral and political organizer. It is the new idol, “the
coldest monster” (Also Sprach, Werke 48), a place where all singularities lose themselves
(Zarathustra 50). The starting point is: “Der Mensch ist eine Sache die überwunden werden
soll” (Zarathustra Manuscripts 11). The chapter “Vom neuen Götzen” is a diatribe against the
state. The state is evil because it controls morality, not only because it is repressive against
life (“Staat nennen sie den langsamen Selbstmord von ganzen Völkern”), but also because it
pushes its subjects in a futile rat race: “Sie klettern übereinander hinaus und werfen sich in
den Abgrund – aber ein Anderer grunzt ihnen schon wieder zu und er stieg noch höher” (71).
The state cannot be reformed. “Only where the state ends, there begins the human being who
is not superfluous: there begins the song of necessity, the unique and inimitable tune”
(Zarathustra 51).
68
2. The Last Revolution
This approach also brings to the fore, as Roberto Esposito has shown, that a
person is characterized by the act of ownership.144 This means to have property
over objects or people-objects, but it also means, for Stirner, to have property
over oneself, to be autonomous. Ruest completed Stirner’s insight by focusing
on work and the protestant ethic. He anticipates Nancy’s position that community
cannot be produced through work (and is inoperative). For Ruest the protestant
ethic of work represented another form of this enslavement of the singularity
and its reduction to a means within a larger scheme of things. In this context—
but also within Marxist discourse145—work was a form of social control and a
useless effort to overcome the despair triggered by the singularity’s production as
subject. Every form of work that was not egotistical was exploitation, Ruest argued
in “Work and Disappointment” (Arbeit und Verzweiflung) (97-99), concluding
that work could only be yours (98).
Work as social control meant control over desire. Subjects were given reasons
to work, and work was advertised as an activity that would instill meaning in the
desert of subjectification. Ruest believed that World War I revealed the absurdity
of metaphysical investments of work and duty. Because death was individual, it
questioned the identification with an abstract askesis of work. In front of death,
which was individual, the singularity understood that nothing was worth dying for.
In war, one worked, fought or died for the state’s interests, and not one’s own.
Ruest constantly returned to the idea of war in order to highlight that humanism
and not man—like Hobbes put it—was evil (50). War represented the ultimate
practice of mobilization: the subject was placing even its own life in the hands
of the state. Nothing could illustrate better the alienating nature of humanism than
the experience of the soldier on the frontline. The solitude of death revealed the
discrepancy between being-human and being-singularity. In this predicament,
the singularity realized that it was to die not in its own name in that of something
that would not die together with it, that is, “man.”
144
145
Roberto Esposito, Persons and Things: From the Body's Point of View. New York: Polity,
2015, 16-19.
According to Ruest, socialism and communism also tried to confer meaning to the social
practice of work. Nevertheless, like other religious discourses, the meaning they came up
with was collective, abstract, extra-individual.
69
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
The Subject of Revolt
A question that Der Einzige answered incompletely—or maybe intentionally
left unanswered—was the question regarding the subject of revolt. Who “owned”
the I (Ich) that decided to revolt, and how individual were the experiences of this
revolt? How could this I escape the ideological apparatuses of the state that had
produced it—what Stirner called the spooks (Sparren) in the subject’s head?
Saul Newman has tried to demonstrate that Stirner’s egotism envisions a
subjectivity that can overcome ideology in an Althusserian sense. It can reach a
point of non-determination “from which resistance to these humanist discourses
can take place” (322).146 In an article titled, Specters of Stirner (an indirect response
to Derrida’s comments on Stirner in Specters of Marx), Newman discovers in Der
Einzige und sein Eigentum a theory of a spectral excess, able to escape ideological
determination and act as a non-essentialist point of departure from which a
critique of ideology may be constructed.
Newman’s reading of Stirner is an effort to go beyond the structuralist and
poststructuralist (Foucauldian theory of power) approaches to ideology (and, I
would add, the state), which posit that “an uncontaminated point of departure
outside ideology is itself ideological.”147 Newman’s piece discusses the Althusserian
contention—also highlighted by Stirner—that there is no human essence beyond
the grasp of ideology, as rationalist Enlightenment thinkers surmised, and that
all human interests are constructed by ideological apparatuses; in short, that the
spooks of ideology are everywhere, existing at the roots of social existence, and
that there is no beyond to ideological interpellation—something that will exist
as the truth that ideology distorts.
Newman’s approach is rightly based on Stirner’s more sophisticated concept
of the state rather than that of other anarchist philosophers. Unlike them, Stirner
understood the state discursively as definition and control over what is (the
146
147
Saul Newman, Specters of Stirner, 322. A parallel between Stirner and Althusser’s view on
statist subject-production reveals surprising similarities. Althusser’s concept of interpellation
resembles Stirner’s Sparren. The former produces the subject, the latter the Mensch. Althusser’s
contentions that the main purpose of ideology is “‘constituting’ concrete individuals as subjects”
(Lenin 116), and that ideology is so pervasive in its constitution of subjects that it forms their
very reality and thus appears to them as “true” or “obvious,” could have been very well taken
out of Stirner’s Der Einzige und sein Eigentum.
Saul Newman, Specters of Stirner, 322.
70
2. The Last Revolution
predicament). Its power is perpetuated by and through its subjects’ actions and
within language and its practice. According to Newman, the liberating potential
of Stirner’s philosophy rests in this investing of the ego with the virtues of a
“counter-ideological specter that escapes subjectification through its resistance
to symbolization.” Newman concludes that
We must, as Stirner suggests, continually work on ourselves to resist ideological
subjectification, and re-negotiate our position in ideology, seeking ‘lines of flight’
from it. Stirner calls this strategy of permanent resistance and renegotiation,
‘ownness’.148 Ownness is a form of positive freedom, in which the individual
re-negotiates his subjectivity, creating his own forms of freedom, rather than it
being handed to him as part of a revolutionary programme.149
Newman thus astutely argues that egotism is a tool of disengagement and of
rendering interpellation superfluous. What he does not deal with is the material
dimension of Stirner’s egotism and the fact that this egotism works on a communal
level as a practice of interrupting the verbal and material perpetuation of ideology.
For Ruest and most of the contributors to Der Einzige,150 this communal dimension
of autonomy, ignored by Newman and many Stirner scholars, was critical in the
act of revolt. The fact that revolt was individual and Empörung egotistical did
not mean that they were solitary endeavors.151 Newman rightly argues that Der
Einzige und sein Eigentum constructs a theoretical “un-man” that can produce a
duly critique of the state and that this “un-man” is not an essence of some sort,
and that it “does not exist in the individual prior to ideological interpellation.
Rather, the ‘un-man’ is a spectral excess produced through the process of interpellation—[which] only comes into being once an ‘essential’ identity is constructed
for the individual.”152 The un-man is thus explored by a rebellion against one’s
own ideologically constructed identity, but again without taking into account
148
149
150
151
152
That is, what I call here sovereignty or autonomy.
Saul Newman, Specters of Stirner, 328.
In Chapter 4, I highlight that one of the contributors who read Stirner in a solitary and idealist
key was Friedlaender/ Mynona.
Stirner’s approach has opened various paths to reading power, which are traceable in the writings
of philosophers of the Frankfurt School or the European post-68 generation. Stirner’s emphasis
on egotism also inspired his detractors. Early critics such as Szeliga and Marx and Engels
misread him as idealist and petty bourgeois. Even in the writings of recent philosophers like
Jacques Derrida, the suspicion of idealism does not fade away.
Saul Newman, Specters of Stirner, 326.
71
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
that this rebellion can succeed only within what Stirner called the Verein der
Egoisten.153
Contributors to Der Einzige believed that individual revolt granted a break
with ideology as a possibility in the present, that is, in the momentous, temporal
and ephemeral act of rebellion itself, and that this practice was not to be performed
in isolation. It was to be achieved within a community of rebels, that is, not only
as subject of rebellion, but also as object of it. Moreover, the singularity existing
in a community without essences, without a discourse on man, was no longer the
object of interpellation. Interpellation rested on an underlying humanizing principle.
As long as there was no Mensch, as long as no we was posited, the mediating agent
who perpetuated ideology was missing. Ideology could not work without identity,
that is, in a community where everybody was a radical other.
Ruest’s antihumanism was thus based on an act of constant de-centering,
inspired by Nietzschean affirmation, which, as Jacques Derrida maintains, is
the joyous affirmation of the play of the world and of the innocence of becoming,
the affirmation of a world of signs without fault, without truth, without origin, which
is offered to an active interpretation. This affirmation [which] determines the
noncenter otherwise than as loss of the center, […] affirms play and tries to pass
beyond man and humanism, the name of man being the name of that being
who, throughout the history of metaphysics or of ontotheology—in other words
throughout his entire history—has dreamed of full presence, the reassuring
foundation, the origin and the end of play.154
This quote harks back to Ruest’s vision of a post-statist politics. In an article
titled “Diogenes and His Lamp” (Diogenes und seine Laterne), Ruest proposed a
Nietzsche-inspired idea of overpolitics—without, however, the Nietzschean aristocratic claims attached to it. This politics was not based on essences, antagonism,
competition and did not lead to war. It was not a politics that antagonized and
killed, but one of letting life live itself as life without transcendent administration
(“Politik des Lebens,” “Überpolitik”). This politics, he concluded, would “seek
people and not bring them together” (110).
There was no unity among the contributors to the journal with regard to the
way in which “de-humanizing” should be practiced. It would be a mistake, however,
153
154
In his reading of Stirner, Gerhard Senft highlights that Stirner did not call for solitary struggle;
only for struggles of solitaries for becoming solitary in common (Schatten 14).
Jacques Derrida, “Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences,” 292.
72
2. The Last Revolution
to surmise that their critique of revolution and their emphasis on rebellious disengagement from state structures functioned according to the logic of reformist
thinking. Even if contributors thought of rebellion as spreading in space and time,
Der Einzige’s understanding of time and agency was different than that of reformism.
Unlike the reform doctrine, which was collectivist, the infection metaphor
assumed that agency was individual and that change was never for the collective, but always for the one. Reformism implied a certain linear and causal
understanding of time and a dialectics of progress, while infection and rebellion
represented phenomena that could not be predetermined and whose effects could
not be predicted. They counted only as phenomena taking place in the present.
For the rebel who rebelled for himself, rebellion was restarted from scratch every
single day. Disengagement was momentary and did not build lasing structures
for the future such as laws, identities or truth. The time of the rebel was discontinuous; it was made of an accumulation of particles of present.
One of the younger contributors to Der Einzige, Arthur Kahane, expressed
his vision of disengagement in a programmatically sounding piece, titled “Manifesto
of the Unique Individual” (Manifest des Einzelnen) (113-114). The article praised
the recluse and the person who did not want to march in a column and for whom
freedom constituted a radical inner experience, a setting, a space in which their
I could breathe freely. The refusal to march in a column represented the refusal
to participate in an alienating experience of time. To be a recluse stood for a
choice to exist in the present. Additionally, the enemies of the singularity, be
they on the Left or on the Right, aimed to trap its thought not only in the timehorizons of the past and the future, of memory and causes to fight for, but also
expose it to calls to unity and to join a multitude (113). As other contributors to
Der Einzige, Kahane made his duty to indicate the abstract and dis-individualized sense of community and time lying behind such calls. Their effect was
a passionate unio mystica of subjects with enslaving misrepresentations of
themselves. This happened not only because the act of misrecognition sheltered
subjects from the active and heroic act of becoming what they were (Nietzsche’s
argument), but especially because they thought and felt within the self-estranging
paradigm of identity and identification (Stirner’s point). As discourse, humanism
appealed to subjects, Kahane argued, because it focused only on those aspects
of the experience of being in common that made things and selves look alike;
because individuals were addicted to identity thinking.
73
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
The Community of Rebels
In spite of the emphasis on rebellion for oneself (and not for others), Der
Einzige argued that rebellion was fulfilled only when practiced in common with
others. Like the bohemian café, Der Einzige itself was such a meeting place of
singularities. It provided the infrastructure for them to assert themselves. It was a
project, a collective one, but one that sought synergy only in the act of rebellion,
not in its content, and even less in time. Every issue could have been the first and
the last, and that it existed testified only to the fact that it was able to attract, but
not organize, a critical mass of rebels.
In order to confer this rebellion in common a more corporeal (and not only
textual) reality, Der Einzige existed also as a discussion group, the Stirnerbund.155
Ruest’s article, “Diogenes and His Lamp,” voiced the call of an association of
rebels, but the call was formulated in such a way as not to suggest the existence
of an overdetermining purpose and of underlying principles of organization.
Ruest made sure to specify that he was not a leader and even less a prophet.
He understood himself only as mediator. The Stirnerbund would be a place of
gathering, and the journal just a collection of self-documents, confessions and
manifestos, as well as a celebration of singularities finding each other.156
Not much information about the group, its members and activities is available.
In its first phase, the group’s “official” name was “Society for tragic culture”
(Gesellschaft der tragischen Kultur). Nevertheless, this sophisticated name did
not last. Its birth was announced in a promotional material titled “A Note to
April 1” (Vermerk zum 1. April) and signed, The Editors (115). The piece was
reflecting on three months of Der Einzige, and was also marking a slight turn in
the interests of the journal. August 1914, the war, and the revolutionary period
were no longer the dominant concerns of the journal. Articles turned toward
more abstract topics. The journal became less polemical and less interested in
addressing present day political issues. Nietzsche’s influence increased, and more
sympathy was shown to late expressionist literary and philosophical positions.
155
156
In November 1919, a publishing house was also founded.
“Und ich selbst will hier Eure eigenen Sammlungen, Eure Ich-Dokumente, Bekenntnisse,
Manifeste, weiter vereinigen, sammeln, sich finden lassen” (109-110).
74
2. The Last Revolution
A change of guard also followed. Hilberseimer and Panarchos left, and new
names like Arthur Kahane, Paul Gurk and Ernst Roy emerged.
The birth of the discussion group was supposed to mark a more constructive
phase in the life of the journal. The fight against “Massensuggestion,” the state,
and the apparatuses that perpetuated it was complemented by a more positive
approach: “the fulfillment of the Schiller-Heine and Stirner-Nietzsche ideal of
tragic Dionysian culture as a replacement of rotten Christian transcendence”
(115).157
Soon, the idea of a society for tragic culture was abandoned. The journal
returned to the appellative “Stirnerbund,” defined as “Interessengemeinschaft
im Stirnerischen Sinne” (143). In this phase, the person in charge of the Bund
was Lehmann; later, the job would be taken by Emil Kauder. Lehmann insisted
on highlighting the dis-organized structure of the group, which aimed at bringing
together revolting Ichs. It was an experiment in community, an alternative to
mass-suggestion, to communion in (religious) belief gymnastics and to party
terror (143).158 Participants, he wrote in a later piece, should understand themselves
as part of something but should not follow anybody or anything. The association
was a place where one “learned” practicing, in common, disobedience, selfaffirmation and the rejection of all inherited and unconditionally adopted collective values, […] templates and mechanics of the spirit (214).159 People gathered
in this Bund to demonstrate that a community of interest could be built without
“ideology, beliefs and catechisms” (215).
Der Einzige published regularly minutes of the meetings of the group.
Lehmann reached out to the university and started the “akademische Gruppe
des Stirnerbundes,” which met for the first time at the Berlin University on
April 11, 1919 (155). The Bund also organized a John Henry Mackay evening,
inviting both Ruest and Lachmann as speakers. It wanted to prove that cooperation
between the two main Berlin individualist anarchist journals was possible and
that Der Einzige was willing to acknowledge the merits of the initiator of the
German individualist anarchist movement.
157
158
159
“Erfüllung des Schiller-Heine’schen, des Stirner-Nietzsche’schen Ideals, tragischer, dionisischer
Kultur in Ablösung der morsch gewordenen christlichen, jeneseitigen.”
“Massensuggestion, Vereinglaubensgymnastik, Parteiterror.”
“Die Ablehnung aller überkommenen, bedingungslos übernommenen Kollektivwerte, [...] der
Schablone, der Geistesmechanik.”
75
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
A report from April 20, 1919, signed Emil Kauder, highlighted that the Bund
was hosting lively debates on themes such as liberty, sovereignty and revolutionary
principles. Kauder outlined Lehmann’s presentation, which criticized the German
student movement for its conformism, patriotism and herd mentality (167).160
The meeting concluded, like several others, with the question, What could be done?
The author’s answer, in the spirit of Der Einzige, was: As a group, nothing special
except setting a breach (167). A more complete answer would come from Ruest
and Friedlaender/ Mynona. The undermining of “Suggestionskräfte” was still high
on the agenda of Der Einzige and its group. On the active side, however, there
was the will to publish books, gather individuals, and even start schools that would
provide libertarian (personalist) education (392). All these efforts were aiming at
spreading the virus of autonomy and “sense of singularity” (329).
The first public meeting of the Bund took place on Monday, May 19, and was
heavily advertised. Its speakers were Lehmann, Lachmann, Ruest, and Friedlaender/
Mynona, that is, the stars of the individualist anarchist press of the time. Ruest’s
talk was then printed in the May 25 issue. The change in tone was here even more
apparent. It was obvious that the journal had become more militant. But even if
Ruest spoke of a Stirner era in philosophy and in the understanding of the political,
which he called, together with the Stirner disciples Henryk Ibsen and Rolf Engert,161
the Dritte Weltepoche, Ruest made sure to keep distance from universalist revolutionary discourse. Even if he beatified Stirner, this new era was not the expression
or the “fulfillment” of a theory. The new history of the new era was open. Stirner’s
legacy needed to be redefined in every moment of the discontinuous time of
this history. The new subjectivity of this era was “a whole, embodied person,
aware of his uniqueness,” who lived in “a new era and world period, which may
be called the third epoch, but which really begins every day, every minute with
me and with you, with my and your simplest decisions” (220).162
160
161
162
Soon the Bund started gaining an identity of its own. The May 18 minutes were framed by an
editors’ comment informing that it was not them who were writing the materials.
In fact, Ibsen and Engert did not use the term “Epoche.” Their phrase was “Das Dritte Reich”
and meant the era of freedom, autonomy and statelessness. Ruest, it seemed, had a premonitory
discomfort with the phrase.
“Ein ganzer, leibhaftiger, seiner Einzigkeit sich bewusster Mensch” […] “einer neuen Epoche
und Weltperiode, welche man die dritte Epoche nennen mag, die aber jeden Tag, jede Minute
mit Mir und mit Dir, mit Meinem und Deinem einfachsten Entschluss des Beginnes auch
wirklich beginnt.”
76
CHAPTER 3
Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
No Voids
When lambasting Werner Sombart’s pro-capitalist individualism in the prewar Die Aktion,163 Friedlaender/ Mynona started from the following premise: it
would be naive to believe that there was such a thing as a free-thinking subject,
or at least that such freedom of thought and choice (Sombart’s utopia) came, as the
promoters of the liberal capitalist state argued, with the air that one breathed.
Sombart was at that time already one of the most prominent social scientists in
Germany. There were three issues at stake in Friedlaender/ Mynona’s critique:
1. he was interested in distancing his brand of individualist anarchism from
liberal/ capitalist individualism; 2. he wanted to emphasize that there were no
such things as ideologically void areas; 3. he argued that only a combination of
individual revolt and theory could serve as a useful guide to individual and public
action. For Friedlaender/ Mynona, “suggestion” was everywhere, in the smallest
particles of signification. Transformed into an agency of micrological coercion,
the state instilled discipline in the most intimate aspects of life, and was permeating
every exchange between its subjects. Power and manipulation were inscribed in
language and in concepts, as well as in the way they produced self-understanding.
Friedlaender/ Mynona’s critique of Sombart’s liberalist optimism synthesized
Der Einzige’s position on the social production of meaning. Friedlaender/ Mynona
and his colleagues at Der Einzige, however, did not react by indulging in ontological and linguistic pessimism, like so many writers of the turn of the century.164
Neither did they adopt expressionist irrationalism or Dada’s destructive approach
to language. In another article, Friedlaender/ Mynona argued that the response
to the crisis of the “Unzulässigkeit aller Worte” was to be found in a personal
163
164
“Wissenschaft und Politik. Ein Wort an Werner Sombart,” Die Aktion, March 14, 1914, 121-126.
The paradigmatic example is Hugo von Hofmannstahl’s Brief des Lord Chandos (1901).
77
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
engagement with theory.165 With a certain degree of variation as to how theory
worked for the singularity, most of the contributors to Der Einzige believed that
revolt without theory was unsustainable, as was theory that was not at the same
time revolt.
The polemic with Sombart’s utopia of the homo economicus continued in
“Once Again: Werther’s Sorrows” (a reply to Sombart’s reply). Sombart proposed
the ideologically void topos of the heart as the organ of “free-choice.” Friedlaender/
Mynona doubted that the heart could function beyond language, as Sombart
fantasized. He argued that if one called “heart” the faculty of decision, the heart
should not “decide” as absolute but inspired by the absolute, that is, by singular
encounters with a self that was posited as absolute. The heart was real, but not
as organ of naïve choice. It had to let itself be inspired by what was purely
subjective, by the self’s absolute nature which, following Kant, was expressed
in the act of legislation. In another article, “Kant and Freedom,” Friedlaender/
Mynona developed his argument in favor of an active and rebellious understanding of freedom (against Sombart’s passive approach), and depicted the
community of the free as one of singularities and as one that had produced and
followed their own law and legislation.166
The answers these essays give to the question of choice, subjectivity, and
agency have only partial relevance in drawing the theoretical profile of Der Einzige
because they are published in a different context. The questions they ask, however,
and especially the framework within which they ask them set the main directions
for what I will discuss in this chapter: Der Einzige’s conception of language and
the journal’s critique of the role of intellectual as mediator of linguistic transactions.
Even if the other contributors to Der Einzige did not share Friedlaender/ Mynona’s
anarchist reading of the categorical imperative (and self-legislation as basis of
autonomy), the latter’s essays reveal not only Der Einzige’s emphasis on the
marriage between revolt and autonomy, but also the journal’s suspicion regarding
the “floating” or “free” intellectual of the bourgeois era. Friedlaender/ Mynona’s
frequent use of the word Gesetz (law) alarmed Ruest, and the categorical imperative
became the bone of contention between him and his brother-in-law; but Ruest
165
166
S. Friedlaender, “Polarität,” 732.
“Der intelligente Wille bringt das Gesetz, nach dem er sich richten muss, selber hervor. Er
gehorcht nicht mehr dem fremden Gesetz der Natur […], sondern den eigenen; und wer dem
eigenen Gesetz gehorcht, der ist frei.” Dr. S. Friedlaender, “Kant und die Freiheit,” 145.
78
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
shared with Friedlaender/ Mynona the idea that a certain theoretical and philosophical muscle was needed to push and develop Stirner’s insights, not so much
to describe the singularity, but to temporarily guide the singularity’s choices.
Ruest trashed the party bureaucrat and the party avant-garde for their
fetishizing of rationality and law and for their universalism. For him, theory did
not explain things, but it was useful in the subject’s assertion as singularity. By
itself, however, theory was not only powerless, but also dangerous. It was
powerless because it could not provide a rupture from the “Bestehende,” and it
was dangerous because of its misuse in universalist contexts. Ruest agreed with
Friedlaender/ Mynona that Sombart’s heart was a fake, a metaphor of social
control, but so was theory (Friedlaender/ Mynona’s proposal), as long as it was
not interrupted by revolt or by counter-theory and subsumed to the experience
of the event.
Ruest’s critique of the intellectual continued Friedlaender/ Mynona’s attack
on ideologically void spaces and on the passive understanding of autonomy. He
and his generation of individualist anarchists also emphasized the singular reading
of theory and the reality of the concept as event. They rejected the utopias of
intersubjectivity and intellectual representation and unraveled the universalist
use and abuse of theory. What they argued instead was, besides the presentism
of individual revolt, a theory of sovereign reading, creative (active) forgetting,
and adventurous experimentation.
Intellectuals
Individualist anarchists also criticized political and intellectual representation,
that is, the assumption that a subject could overcome its individual interest and
speak/ write in the service of universal truth and in the name of others. For Der
Einzige, the “betrayal of the intellectuals” was thus twofold. On the one hand,
as Julien Benda argued in his eponymous book, the intellectuals fell prey to
nationalist passions, abandoned their “disinterested” view of history and their
commitment to universals, and functioned as agents of mobilization. This practice
gained salience during the glorious days of August 1914 and their repetition
in 1919. But that was just the tip of the iceberg. On the other hand, Ruest and
his comrades found Benda’s emphasis on intellectual disinterest and quest for
79
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
universals as problematic and pernicious as participation in the nationalist
delirium.
Universalism was just another cause, another form of mobilization, which
stood in contradiction with Der Einzige’s quest for singularity and self-possession.
Predictably, Der Einzige’s anti-universalism was continuing Stirner und Nietzsche’s
positions, something that was highlighted by Ruest in an article titled “Stirner
and Nietzsche”: truth was a fabrication employed in keeping the singularity at
bay, and universals were tools of the state deployed to engender the subject’s
inferiority and dependency on organization (6).
Ruest could not argue with Benda. The latter’s book appeared after the demise
of Der Einzige. Ruest, however, confronted the universalist tradition that Benda
represented. According to Seth Taylor, one of his targets was Kurt Hiller’s understating of intellectuals as a freethinking avant-garde (that is, not part of the party
bureaucracy), capable of leading the working class towards emancipation.167
Hiller and Ruest’s biographies had many touch points. Like Ruest, Hiller had
broken with Franz Pfemfert’s Die Aktion in the pre-war period and edited his
own publication. Like Ruest, he adopted Nietzsche’s radicalism, but their readings
did not overlap. Hiller’s response to the intellectual brainwashing of the last years
of the Wilhelmine era (imperial era) led to a more “constructive” approach, which
he called activism or volunteerism. He professed the intellectual activist as
consensus builder. The agency he advocated—the intellectual worker, Geistige
Arbeiter (or simply Geistige)—was guided by the normative goal of the (Hegelian)
Geist,168 and was, as Taylor stresses, “in a position to determine society’s goals
precisely because [it] stood above party interest.”169
Pfemfert had accused Hiller of elitism.170 In 1919, the former’s protégé and
future KPD and Dada wunderkind Carl Einstein ridiculed Hiller’s activism from
the perspective of the new revolutionary Left. In articles such as “To the Intellectuals”
(An die Geistigen) or “Intellectual Proletarians or the System of Incapacitation
(Intellektuelle und Proletarier oder das System der Entmündigung), he attacked
Hiller’s activism from the traditional Marxist perspective of the revolutionary role
of the proletariat. Arguing, like Der Einzige, for a post-World War I ideological
167
168
169
170
See Seth Taylor, Left-Wing Nietzscheans, 157.
Anthony Phelan, The Weimar Dilemma, 21.
Seth Taylor, Left-Wing Nietzscheans, 68.
“Soldaten! Kameraden der A.S.P., Freunde der Aktion,” 587.
80
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
tabula rasa, Einstein concluded that intellectuals as promoted by Hiller are “the
mental brothel of the bourgeoisie” (das Gehirn-Bordell des Bürgertums) and
needed to be eradicated.171
Ruest’s critique started from a different premise. In an article I discussed before
“Where Are the Intellectuals?” Ruest bluntly responded, like Einstein, to the question
in the title: “I’m telling you, nowhere.” (13). His position was, however, not grounded
in class struggle. Ruest was as critical of universalism as he was of the Marxian
cajolement that philosophers should cease participating in the word game of
interpreting the world and start changing it. For Ruest, the “world” as unity did
not exist. Acknowledging a concept like the “world” meant accepting structures
of organization. Besides being a homogenizing and mobilizing discourse, class
struggle falsely divided society in oppressors and oppressed. Oppression was
structural and resided in the existence of the state and collectivities themselves
and in the illusion of the “world” they engendered. Everybody was a loser as a
member of an organized community—not only the working class, but also rulers
and the bourgeoisie. From this point of view, class struggle, Ruest realized (as
did later proponents of the New Left like Antonio Negri), stood in the service
of the perpetuation of the state order.
“Where Are the Intellectuals?” traced the way in which a thinker like Hiller
constructed a humanist discourse. It investigated the intersubjective ground that
would allow the Geistige to universalize. Ruest read Hiller’s activism as part of
a social division of labor. Based on the Marxian humanism of work—one of
those essences that Ruest rejected—Hiller advocated that the guiding mission
of the intellectual was legitimate because it was part of a collective and socially
divided effort towards emancipation. For Hiller, there was such a thing as Geist
as opposed to matter, and there had to be someone to administer it, the “geistige
Arbiter.”
Confronted with such a portrayal of intellectuals, Ruest questioned its legitimacy and asked how could the Geistige administer the Geist of others, both as
singularity and as multiple. He also wondered what did division of labor say
about the way in which the intellectual conceived of himself or herself and the
Geist it administered, and on what basis would the represented agree to feel
represented. These questions triggered him to notice two Stirnerian “spooks”
171
Carl Einstein, “Intellektuelle und Proletarier oder das System der Entmündigung,” 159.
81
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
haunting Hiller’s thought. First was the spook of representation, and second, the
spook of intellectual autonomy and universal thinking within an organized and
mobilized society.
There was no such thing as only one logic, Ruest argued. There were an
infinite number of logics corresponding to each singularity (he gave Hamlet as
an example of such particular logic that did not overlap with that of others around
him). If the laborers of spirit argued that they were in possession of something
that was true and present in the poly-idiomatic logic of the multiple, a Nietzschean
reading grounded in the will to power made this assumption look controversial.
But there was more Ruest had to say. Universalism and the regime of truth were
not only the effect of hegemonic signifying practices or cynical manipulation of
knowledge by a truth-administering intelligentsia, but also its cause. The real
problem rested in the fact that the regime of truth (which was also the regime of
organization) was administering the intellectuals’ thinking and was turning them
into its agents. In the organized community, the presupposition of the universal
(Geist) acted as a power vector, disciplined the Geistige’s utterances and framed
them in such a way as to privilege identity over difference. What intellectuals
imagined as spontaneous and free dialogue of ideas was for Ruest “suggeriert”
(15). Their creative tasks were intuitive acts of adaptation (Anpassung) (15), and
their so-called independent and dialectical thinking was just the mark of their role
as socializers, producers of word games and conceptual buzz (Begriffsverwirrung),
as well as performers of ideology.
Such a procedure, however, was possible because state organization created
the spectacle (via humanism) of a certain model of (human) interaction founded
on intersubjectivity. Against Hegel and Hiller, Ruest argued that Geist was always
singular and utterly contingent upon a particular corporeal being. The materiality
of the singularity granted it. Universalists like Hegel and Hiller invented this
division between matter and spirit and dialectics (division of labor) in order to
overcome the interruption of singularity and contain it.172 Ruest argued that the
appeal to the Geist was a reaction to the threat posed to the ordering mind by
the unorganized multiplicity. The Geist was born out of the fear of the other,
and its proclamation as a superior entity emerged from the effort to contend this
172
“Schon an und für sich aber steht Geistiges und Körperliches immer nur im Verhältnis des
Lenkenden und des Gelenkten” (Wo sind die Geistigen? 16).
82
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
uncontrollable being (Vereinigung).173 The other was interpellated as Geist and
body separately in order to legitimize a two-level social and political manipulation.
Otherwise, why would the intellectual need such abstractions like the spirit, Ruest
asked? Because the energies of the battalions of workers scared him to death, the
Geistige quickly called for containment and socialization (15).
Arguing for the singularity of the Geist and the lack of division between
spirit and matter became, in the lineage of Stirner, the pillar of Ruest’s political
resistance. Egotism disenchanted the world from the spook of the Geist. In
Stirner’s words: “The egotist will dissolve the spirit [and the spirit-matter
divide] in his nothingness” (77).174 “Unification,” as the production of masses
and mass-objects, and the appeals to Geist and to universalizing discourses did
not bring liberation, because strong was, for Ruest, not the multitude but the
singular (16).175 The only Vereinigung that Ruest could accept was against this
divisive operation of power—a multitude of assertive singularities.176
In the novel Graue Magie (1922), Friedlaender/ Mynona, by this time already
converted to idealism, depicted Ruest’s insistence on the indefinable nature of the
self. Anselm Ruest was identified as Dr. Amsel Orest and Der Einzige as “Der
Insler” (The Islander) and described as concerned with indeterminacy and the
vitality of the singularity.177 Orest’s intellectual project was the promoting of
this “neither-nor” subjectivity or the undifferentiated self. This active thrust of
indeterminacy (Indifferenz) into the political discourse would lead, Orest believed,
to an implosion of the determined, differentiated and organized world.178 In terms
173
174
175
176
177
178
“Hat er nicht immer das bloß Zahlenmässige, das Quantitaive, Physis, die Materie (nehmen
wir einmal die ganz entgeistete) beherrscht?” (Wo sind die Geistigen? 15)
Egotism and revolt become the countertactics to the spooky works of the Geist: “Darum
verachtest Du den Egoisten, weil er das Geistige gegen das Persönliche zurücksetzt und für
sich besorgt ist, wo Du ihn einer Idee zu Liebe handeln sehen möchtest. Ihr unterscheidet
Euch darin, dass du den Geist, er aber Sich zum Mittelpunkte macht” (41).
“Nicht Vieles ist stark: stark sein kann nur Eines, das Eine, das Individuelle.”
“Ich berufe mich auf eine Unio, die jeder Einzelne in seinem Ich, seinem Geist, seiner Einzigkeit
mit sich herumträgt—, auf eine Einheit die Jeglicher auf dem Grunde kennt, wenn er des
geheimnisvollen Willens, das seine Glieder bewegt, und der nicht viel komplizierter (denn er
ist ohne Teile) auch die Lenkung aller Weltdinge besorgen könnte, gedenkt…” (16).
Ruest “wollte nämlich nichts als lebendig sein und wirken, und da das Leben synthetisch
undefinierbar ist, rund, verflössend, Weder-noch, zum Beispiel weder Leib noch Seele, sondern
bereits zusammen: so ließ auch Amsel sich nicht definieren, war nicht fassbar, und hatte an
dieser ‘Lebendigkeit’ seine Delikatesse.”
“Hielte es nur jeder so—dann wäre (ohne Gesetz, ohne Staat, anarchisch) allen geholfen!”
Mynona, Graue Magie, 98.
83
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
of language, Orest aimed at undermining structures of differentiation by employing
a fluid, “gelatinous” understanding of language and concepts. Opposed to humanism,
“Amsel valued the difference between you and I” and “sought to replace the absent
community with ‘life’, indistinction, slime, [and] jelly” fearing ideas of law and
precision.179
Since Hiller’s intellectual “represented,” this representation constructed the
represented object as mass-multitude. The multiple was interpellated as the same
by the mobilizing discourse of the Geistige. This engendering of brotherhoods
and sisterhoods in the name of collective causes outraged Ruest. In another article,
criticizing the intellectual demise that happened on the eve of World War I (“—aber
lügt nur nicht zu sehr!”), Ruest argued that it was the state-structure that created
the intellectual. The intellectuals’ pro-war delirium was not the expression of an
error of the mind or of human wickedness. The reality of organized communities
heroicized intellectuals’ profiles and endowed them with the authority to speak
for the many. In response to this situation, the basic question that had to be asked
was whether this or that intellectual, arguing for a common cause, was truly
speaking in my name, and whether I was just passively, structurally accepting
this predicament.
Whose song of praise did sing and still sings this well-known and ‘true-human’
poet and poet-man, [...] applauded and adored by all peoples? Yours or mine
[...]? Or do you not feel, at least now, that this “un-human” did not really mean
you or me, but some bloodless rambling timeless ghost, the “high” schemes of
the common man who had never been your true human brother? (50)180
179
180
“…suchte die fehlende Gemeinsamkeit [i.e. the Vereinigung performed by power] durch
‘Leben,’ Verschwimmung, Schleim, Gallerte zu ersetzen, “ängstigte sich von Gesetz, Abstraktion,
Präzision und vermochte so, ein Wesen zu machen, das eine Verwandtschaft mit den Ideen
des Justemilieu zeigte.” Mynona, Graue Magie, 98-99. The singularity was spirit and matter.
The singularity was both at the same time and none. It was neither a sole cerebral being (as
for Descartes or Fichte) nor a tabula rasa produced by the environment or by relations of
production as for positivists or socialists. The ego, as understood by Ruest (through Stirner),
was an impure mixture of corporeality, emotions and intellect: “Hingegen für den ‘Einzigen’
ist das Ich die wirkliche reale Substanz, konkret und persönlich erlebbar. Suchen Sie, Herr
Doktor Stern, tieferes als die Realität? Ich nicht” (28).
“Wen sang und singt dieser allbekannte, dieser bei allen Völkern […] beklatschte, in den Himmel
erhobene, “echt menschliche” Poet und Dichtersmann? Etwa Dich und Mich […] oder fühlst
Du nicht wenigstens jetzt, wie dieser Unmensch gar nicht Dich oder Mich gemeint hat, sondern
irgend ein blutleeres klapperdurres Gespenst der Jahrhunderte, jenen “hohen” Schemen des
allgemeinen Menschen der noch keines Menschen leibhafter Bruder gewesen?!”
84
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
The pre-war era proved that the involvement of the intellectual in creating such
Bruderschaften was extensive. In August 1914, these “poets” wrote 1.5 million
war poems. Mobilized by state propaganda, people took to the streets and sang
hymns of praise to the Kaiser and patriotic songs. The Second International
failed to oppose the war and the SPD disregarded its pre-war commitment that
workers would not kill each other for the interests of their masters. Few leftist
journals adopted outspoken anti-war positions,181 and few German intellectuals
opposed it from its very beginning, among them only Ernst Bloch, Kurt Hiller,
Richarda Huch, Gustav Landauer, Karl Kraus, and Heinrich Mann.182
The August 1914 experience demonstrated that both party-affiliated and “freefloating” intellectuals were powerless when faced with state structures. What more
often happened was that they were co-opted by these structures sometimes to the
point of ecstatic identification with the role of promoter of state interest. The
question was then how could one escape such structural “suggestion”? Besides
revolt, Ruest recommended askesis. Intellectuals (individuals in general) should
resist the temptation of speaking in others’ name. They should give up talking
to man, and start talking to singularities. They should give up the temptation of
power, of leadership, and of authority, as well as of putting themselves into the
service of building “operative” communities in a narrative of progress.
The Symbolic Order
Antihumanism as critique and as affirmation of the uncontainable singularity
was the tool that Der Einzige used to fracture the homogeneity of the “communities
of brothers and sisters”—Bruderschaften. In line with this was the questioning
of communication and intersubjectivity. Bruderschaft assumed identity of thought
and feeling among its members. The transmission of knowledge from the center
(the subject) to individual recipients (the object) was expected to function smoothly,
allowing concepts to pass from one location to the other and be signified similarly.
181
182
Only Pfemfert’s Aktion and Rene Schikele’s Weisse Blätter (Mommsen 33).
See Kurt Flasch, Die geistige Mobilmachung, 230. Th. Mann’s war excitement proved how “holy”
the war was for many German intellectuals. “Why should the artist, the artist as soldier, not
have praised God for the collapse of a peaceful world with which he was fed up, so fed up?
War. It was a holy purification, a redemption which we felt, and an enormous hope” (quoted
in Mommsen 25).
85
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
Der Einzige’s position was that of regarding modern media-increased intersubjectivity and signification not as an achievement but as a constant failure. Once
humanism was abandoned, communication, concepts, consensus, dialogue, and
other constitutive values of traditional intellectual approach would come under
questioning too. Where the organizing intellectual saw community, consensus,
and smoothness, the individualist anarchist saw difference, fractures, and dissociation. Moreover, the idea of the sovereign singularity emerged out of this
moment of discontinuity. Autonomous thought constituted itself within this breech
in communication. Since nothingness was the foundation of every singularity,
their interaction, Ruest argued, could not assume an accurate reproduction of
meaning (51). Thus, there was no such thing as a universal intersubjectivity
between two radical singularities. When it was posited, it was with the purpose
of creating identity and turning symbolization into a subjecting practice.
Many anarchist voices spoke up against various aspects of the subjecting nature
of language, concepts, and signification. The thesis that, within the modern liberal
state, subjection was done not only via law and law-enforcement, but also via
control over symbols went back to the earliest anarchists. In God and the State,
Bakunin argued that struggles for emancipation needed to gain in complexity since
the control of the modern state was primarily over signification.183 However, only
individualist anarchists of later generations turned Bakunin’s intuitions into subtler
inquiries into the mechanics of language and highlighted the immanent structures
of oppression at work within the symbolic order.
For Stirner, everything boiled down to the rise of the Geist and its appropriation by the state as the modern tool of subjection, fascinatingly depicted by
Hegel. Hegel had brought concepts (Begriffe) as religious and spooky tools to
dogmatic perfection.184 Influenced by Stirner, Gustav Landauer stressed the alienating effect of concepts. Signifiers were abstract, that is, detached from history,
and, unlike living bodies, they did not bear the mark of time. They were, in a way,
a negation of life. In his essay “Something on Morality” (Etwas über Moral),
Landauer emphasized this mortifying nature of concepts, referring to them as
domineering, oppressive, and loaded with hatred of freedom.185
183
184
185
Mikhail Aleksandrovich Bakunin, God and the State, viii.
Max Stirner, Der Einzige und sein Eigentum, 104.
“Die menschlichen Begriffe sind schwächlich, in der Zeit vergänglich, hinfällig: darum sind sie
herrsüchtig, unterdrückungswütig, freiheitsfeindlich.” Gustav Landauer, Auch die Vergangenheit
ist Zukunft, 43.
86
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
For Hans Blücher, a collaborator of Der individualistische Anarchist, language
came under critical scrutiny because of its instrumental role in organizing communities. Since language was such an important organizing tool, political disobedience had to work at its level too. Like Ruest, Blücher looked back at August
1914 to understand the way in which language became instrumental in building
the state as war-machine, and tracked the workings of concepts. The intellectual
was for him the culprit as well. The intellectual hunted free-circulating signifiers,
turned them into concepts and integrated them into a system.186 The cultural
word game was the game of selection, accommodation, and integration of the
signifiers with the interests of the state machine. The intellectual perpetuated the
infestation of society with concepts, and the system worked because integration
also meant hiding the subjecting character of the concept. In their labor of universalizing, intellectuals also rendered invisible the disciplining function of language.
This erasure enabled coercion and prescriptive modes pass as descriptive. The
intellectual’s work is to smoothen the transition from “you should accept” to
“there is.” The intellectual and philosopher’s “Meistertrick” was that of making
the questions “Why?” or “On whose behalf?” hard or even impossible to pose.187
Blücher even tried to provide a tactics against this conceptual inoculation of
the public sphere and proposed a “Gegengift” derived from Stirner and Benjamin
Tucker’s theories of resistance: active ignorance. Once people did not obey the law
any more, the law made no sense and lost its power. He imagined a conceptual
general strike. The concept should be ignored, and chaos, the undetermined,
indifference should be placed at the center of singularities’ interaction188
Blücher’s colleague and editor of Der individualistische Anarchist, Benedict
Lachmann, was also keen on remarking that the rendering intersubjective of
individual consciousness by statist humanism was the ideal tool for subjection.
Intersubjectivity was tantamount to oppression and granted the domination of
the world and of singularities with the concept. Men and women had to realize—
Lachmann argued in his book on Stirner—that they lived in a world of misunderstanding. The way in which each singularity used a concept was different.
186
187
188
Heinz Blücher, “Verstaatlichung des Menschen oder Vermenschlichung des Staates,” 223.
Heinz Blücher, “Verstaatlichung des Menschen oder Vermenschlichung des Staates,” 223.
“Die einzigste Möglichkeit, einen Begriff zu töten, ist, sich keine Mühe mehr geben, ihn zu
begreifen.” Heinz Blücher, “Verstaatlichung des Menschen oder Vermenschlichung des Staates,”
223.
87
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
Individuals had to be reminded the trivial fact that no two acts of signification
produced the same result and that to believe in ideas means in fact to believe in
an idea of an idea, which is in fact a “double spook, a labyrinth of nonsense and
madness.”189 Lachmann’s book ended by drawing an important conclusion for
individualist anarchist resistance:
This impossibility of reaching an agreement on the conception of the judgments
of value of others, which, it seems to me, is the strongest and most common
foundation of egotism, has not yet been taken up by anybody, including Stirner,
in the realm of investigation.190
Theory of Events
Philosophy, as the practice of clarifying concepts, came under Ruest’s ridicule.
In an article titled “Der Einzige defends Itself as Egotist” (Der Einzige bewährt
sich als Egoisten) he responded to two letters to the editor, which he reproduced
at the beginning of his piece. Both letters came from people who referred to
themselves as philosophers, and who raised objections with regard to the way
in which Ruest and Stirner used the concept Ich. Dr. Fritz Stern addressed the
logical and theoretical malfunction of the Stirnerian understanding of the self.
Stern seemed a defendant of individualism. He drew on Fichte and opposed Fichte’s
Ich, as the relationship of conscience to itself, to Stirner and Ruest’s who, according
to Stern, regarded it as nature, that is, as more than its discursive representation.
The two letters asked Ruest to clarify concepts, a provocation an individualist
anarchist intellectual could not take on.191 Accepting a theoretical discussion
meant recognizing the regime of Geist, intersubjectivity and the practices of
consensus-building such as the “disinterested dialogue,” that is, the reconciliation
of the irreconcilable on humanist presuppositions. For Ruest, Dr. Stern inhabited
an environment in which one could find the time and the peace to clarify concepts,
189
190
191
“Denn an ‘Ideen’ glauben, heißt in Wahrheit: an die ‘Idee’ glauben, die Ich Mir von Deiner
“Idee” mache! Ein Spuk, ein Doppelspuk, ein Labyrinth von Unsinn und Wahnwitz.” Benedict
Lachmann, Protagoras, Nietzsche, Stirner, 71.
“Diese Unmöglichkeit, eine Verständigung über die Auffassung der Werturteile eines Anderen
zu erlangen, diese, wie mir scheint, stärkste und natürlichste Begründung des Egoismus, ist noch
von Keinem, auch von Stirner nicht, in den Bereich der Untersuchungen gezogen worden.” Benedict
Lachmann, Protagoras, Nietzsche, Stirner, 71.
The other letter came from the socialist philosopher Arthur Goldstein.
88
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
follow logical threads, strive for the accuracy of statements, and detail demonstrations.
This was the comfort zone of Order under the shelter of the Law. To such an idyllic
imagining of disinterested thinking (“die Klärungen theoretischer Fragen in seinem
Hause” (26)), Ruest proposed an understanding of thinking that performed its
operations in the haste and turmoil of the battlefield (“tumultuarischen Zeiten”),
within a “war of all against all.” The illusion of universalism could emerge only
in the literary salon or in the academic seminar room, but not when encountering
irreconcilable singularities.
Ruest acknowledged the temptation of buying into the philosopher or intellectual’s role and of participating in the social ritual of clarifying and integrating
concepts.192 He adopted, however, Landauer and Lachmann’s position against
the mortifying nature of concepts and the fear of the unknown they carried, even
if he was aware that he was in part contradicting himself. His anarchism was
philosophical, and his immanentism—being non-conceptual within the regime
of concepts—was often close to self-contradiction and hypocrisy.
What made it authentic is perhaps explained by Rudolf Rocker, one of Germany’s
most popular anarchists. In his memoirs, he synthesizes the platform of the French
theoretical anarchist journal En Dehors as follows:
We love the fight for the sake of combat, without taking into account the benefits
of a winning idea. There is no infallible touchstone for the truth yet, and the ideal
of a coming Golden Age has not yet been revealed. Life itself is an eternal
change of ideas and phenomena that are not bound to any particular formation.
We feel driven by new thoughts today and do not know where they are going to
take us. It is the movement itself that changes all forms of existence and breaks
new ground. Nothing is worse than the absolutism of ideas that pretend to be
able to explain the world according to certain models. Every absolutism is a
reaction and a sin against the spirit. That's why we only live today and do not ask
what the future will bring to us. We only know the fetters that push us today,
and they have to be blown up.193
192
193
“Ich habe mich an diesen “Klärungen” nach besten Kräften beteiligt, aber meines Wissens
nie einen Zweifel darüber bestehen lassen [...], dass ich diese Klärungen keineswegs in alle
Ewigkeit fortzusetzen gedächte, sondern mit der etwa einmal geklärten “theoretischen Fragen”
mit gemeinster Schlichtheit und brutalen Egoismus zu meinem Nutz und Frommen bedienen
würde” (26).
“Wir lieben den Kampf um des Kampfes willen, ohne auf die Vorteile Bezug zu nehmen, die
der Sieg einer Idee mit sich bringt. Es gibt bis jetzt keinen unfehlbaren Prüfstein für die Wahrheit,
und das Ideal eines kommenden Goldenen Zeitalters ist noch nicht entschleiert worden. Das
89
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
This platform which could have been published by Der Einzige on its front page
and could have been signed by Ruest or Lehmann highlighted the ambiguous
relationship of individualist anarchism with theory and concepts. Dialectics and
thought anchored solely in the present allowed an excuse for the necessary selfcontradiction of the egotist and could explain why Ruest was not hypocritical when
he declared himself both a revolted egotist and a philosopher and manipulator
of concepts. But dialectics and presentism also challenged the possibility of
knowledge. They suggested that thought developed only in the present. Based
on the refusal of unity, they criticized the functioning of thinking, even of the
legitimacy of asking oneself philosophical questions, as the question implied
looking into the future.
But an overall refusal of knowledge, of concepts and of intellectual exchange
was not something that one would find in the pages of Der Einzige. Der Einzige
defended its theoretical position by arguing that there was no knowledge that a
singularity or a community had to possess. There was no constitutive text like a
bible or a constitution that a community of rebels needed, which was essential
to the subject’s self-understanding. Their criticism against the organizing power
of concepts did not mean, however, refusal tout court. The intervention of the
journal was the best proof that ideas needed to be fought at least in part with
ideas. Der Einzige did not advocate irrationalism or silence; it only advocated
certain practices of dealing with concepts. An Ich without concepts was defenseless in the face of ideology. Unconnected or atomized selves could be as easily
manipulated as those who identified with causes. This was why the journal existed,
and this was also why it tried, in a different and non-authoritarian way, to “bring
singularities together.” Concepts and knowledge were double-edged swords: tools
for both submission and liberation.
If one wants to elicit an answer to Der Einzige’s take on concepts, and, more
generally, to its mission as a concepts-producing journal, one needs to return to
Leben selbst ist ein ewiger Wechsel der Ideen und Erscheinungen, die an keine bestimmte
Auffassung gebunden sind. Wir fühlen uns heute von neuen Gedanken ergriffen und wissen
nicht, wohin sie uns tragen werden. Es ist die Bewegung selbst, die alle Formen des Daseins
ändert und neuen Möglichkeiten Bahn bricht. Nichts ist schlimmer als der Absolutismus der
Ideen, die da vorgeben, die Welt nach bestimmten Vorlagen unmoldeln zu können. Jeder
Absolutismus ist Reaktion und Sünde gegen den Geist. Deshalb leben wir nur das Heute und
fragen nicht danach, was uns die Zukunft bringen wird. Wir kennen nur die Fesseln, die uns
heute drücken, und sie gilt es zu sprengen.” Rudolf Rocker, Aus den Memorien eines deutschen
Anarchisten, 114. Rocker did not actually believe in this platform.
90
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
Ruest’s phrase of “tumultuarische Zeiten” and its reference to the epistemological
disorder in which the singularity processed the what is. Ruest’s irony regarding
the philosophical seminar was aimed at a certain utopia of knowledge (and polity)
that strove towards ideals of order, clarity, non-contradiction, and purity. History
had shown and would show how destructive such thinking was. The more order,
unity and purity a system engendered at its core, the more destructive it became
at its margins and in its encounter with the Others that it produced. Thinking in
tumultuous times meant accepting the impurity, the temporality, and the improvised character of thought. It meant acknowledging the temporality of concepts as
events,194 as engendering and arresting contradictory forces that change directions
and intensities when wandering, as signifiers from one mind to another. Instead
of transmitting or organizing, concepts “collided” with others, “destabilized,”
“inspired,” opened and closed doors, and were at the same time causes and objects
of intellectual plundering, ridicule and abuse.
Tumultuous times revealed the agonic epistemological context of conceptual
production (in the chaotic struggle of all against all). Nevertheless, this predicament also emphasized the improvised and creative aspect of the process. If a
concept’s function was to name something, to carry with it some sort of personal
referentiality, it also had another function, that of separating as forgetting and
overcoming. This was the creative and rebellious potential in the employment
of the concept, and this is why Der Einzige expressed so much interest in the act
of creation, in genius, Rausch (ecstasy), and especially, in Nietzsche’s concept
of active and creative forgetting—all in relation to the idea of individual revolt
and its emphasis on the present.195
One of the most dedicated promoters of this positive and non-dialectical
idea of rebellion was Friedlaender/ Mynona. He published both theoretical and
fictional pieces dealing with this topic. His novella, Der Schöpfer, appeared in
installments in Der Einzige, filling four issues of the Beiblatt, while his philosophical pieces, though with a thrust slanted towards idealism, continued his
194
195
As Deleuze in Guattari would later use the term in What is Philosophy?.
For Stirner, it is ignoring the spooks in one’s mind. Nietzsche develops his theory of creative
forgetting in his famous essay “On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life.” Continuing
Stirner’s ghostly vocabulary, he calls for the abandonment of the past because it “returns as a
ghost and disturbs the peace of a later moment” (61). For Der Einzige, creative forgetting is
revolt, impertinent demeanor with regard to history (that is, selective and not submissive), and
allowing the subject to think ahistorically, in the present.
91
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
pre-war “presentism” and “indifferentism.” Already in his Schöpferische Indifferenz,
Friedlaender/ Mynona argued that “unlearning to relate superstitiously to existence
is the propaedeutic to the act of creation.”196 In a piece titled “Imitative” (signed
S. Friedlaender), Friedlaender/ Mynona expressed his view on “tumultuous times.”
Truly tumultuous were the times that could liberate the genius of the individual.
For Friedlaender/ Mynona, everybody was and had genius, and could overcome,
creatively and non-dialectically, the Bestehende. Living in tumultuous times
meant living as if one had genius, as if one could reach to a point beyond
differences, beyond conceptuality, and re-create the world according to one’s
own. Becoming genius, Friedlaender/ Mynona wrote in another article, was synonymous to becoming self; to taking one’s fate in one’s hands, setting oneself as
ultimate goal and understanding that beyond the Ich in which one was “thrown”
rested only the Nichts.197
Only the person who has the courage to disregard all known knowledge has among
many qualifications also that of a philosopher198 (315).
Knowledge was thus approached from a different angle than usual: as a burden.
The effort to “improve” knowledge or “expand” it, was, as Ruest’s critique of
the intellectual revealed, a participation in a ritual of social control. Instead of
being part of the ordering process, Friedlaender/ Mynona prescribed forgetting—
making oneself a tabula rasa of all conceptual arsenal one is given (and the
structures of difference they engender) (112). Forgetting was essential, as Blücher
also emphasized, for escaping the vicious circle of ideology and to rethink ethics
and politics.
Ernst Roy, another wunderkind of Der Einzige, also developed his notion of
tumultuous times in a series of articles. The concept he proposed was Rausch
(intoxication, euphoria and intensity). In the spirit of the industrial revolution,
the time of Rausch was concentrated time. Rausch meant schizophrenic rupture
from history. It was a strategy of liberatory forgetting and of envisioning oneself in or as the center of the world (221). Roy followed his guru Friedlaender/
Mynona, but unlike Friedlaender/ Mynona, he was more concerned with the
196
197
198
“Das Verlernen des Aberglaubens an das Vorhandene ist die Propädeutik zur Schöpfung.”
Salomo Friedlaender, Schöpferische Indifferenz, 322.
“Nietzsche und Strauß—immer wieder” (314-316).
“Nur der Mensch, der den Mut hat, auf alles bekannte Wissen zu pfeifen, hat unter vielen
Befähigungen auch diejenige zum Philosophen” (315).
92
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
idea of accelerated existence than with the present. For him, Rausch was not
only intoxication but also intensity. His position seemed to mix individualist
anarchism with futurism (whose manifesto was published in 1909). It regarded
the subject as a machine. Tumultuous times represented a context that could
stimulate mental acceleration and exponentially increase the subject’s productivity.
It was this acceleration that could lead to the fall of all barriers and inhibitions
of the mind and allow limitless creation—the true and heroic virtue of the genius
(233, 280).199
Daimonides—who mainly contributed to the Beiblatt—also highlighted
the relationship between creative forgetting and revolt, following his mentor’s
(Friedlaender/ Mynona) equation, genius = rebel = philosopher. In a series of
aphorisms, Daimonides synthesized the theory of creative forgetting, arguing
that one is not a blank page, but a “tabula rasa”—that is, not pure void, but a
palimpsest, something that had already been written upon, and that creatively
(selectively, turning memory against itself) erased the previously written and thus
appropriated it non-dialectically. Originality and autonomy, another aphorism
suggested, were connected to criminality, that is, to the act of destroying-ignoringforgetting of the past and the established order (119).
Dealing with Concepts
Ruest developed his theory of writing in tumultuous times in “Now for the
Fourth Time: Revolution—a School Program!” (Und zum 4. Mal: Revolution—
ein Schulprogramm!”) (121-126). He was here at his most revolted. His piece
addressed a multitude of issues. The piece was programmatically chaotic because
it was designed to build a contrast with the words “school” and “program” in its
title. In terms of style, it was close to incomprehensible, but this turbulent
idiom was willingly employed in order to express singularity and the fact that
the author was in possession of his “Sprache.”200 What it staged was a dramatic
199
200
For Roy, the embodiment of this intense genius was Nietzsche.
Ruest addressed his readers directly in the second person, capitalizing the informal secondperson pronoun Du in order to highlight their sovereignty as egos encountering the text. The
polite form of the second person, Sie, was avoided, probably because it involved an artificial
I to I relationship, inscribed with social codes. The capitalization of Du put the accent on the
reader as a radical other. Capitalized Du underscored the hiatus in the transmission of information
93
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
struggle with concepts, use and abuse of theory, an mix of the personal and the
public in logic and communication. The idea of rebellion in language was transmitted by words, by representation, but it was also directly enacted in Ruest’s
perplexing sentences, in syntax and in the agonic style that dashed from one
frontline to another. The text not only prescribed egotism and revolt; it performed
them. After all, this was what Der Einzige was all about: disobedience, egotism,
impertinence, rebellion—displayed, exemplified, and to a certain extent, theorized.
In writing, performance as Bakuninian “propaganda by the deed” mattered as
much as the meaning of the generated words.
In “For the Fourth Time…” Ruest battled with the idea of representation
and the illusion of empowerment it brought about. He also attacked the school
system, which he described as a place where one was not only taught to obey,
but also to believe that there were people who could know one’s problems better
than oneself. In addition, he criticized intellectual division of labor and then
embarked on a quest for the precursors and theoreticians of disobedience in German
culture, drawing a pedigree for Der Einzige that included romantic poets like
Friedrich Schiller and Heinrich Heine, and philosophers like Nietzsche, Marcus,
and Friedlaender.201
Once this “tradition” had been established, Ruest made sure to remind his
audiences that he did not intent to create a canon, and added that these names
have been highlighted not with the purpose to be adored and their writings
obeyed.202 He targeted the transmission and administration of knowledge, and
called for an end of philosophy as apparatus of organization of knowledge.
Knowledge, Ruest had learnt from Stirner, needed to die and be reborn as
will.203 It needed to be forgotten and then re-appropriated in textual acts of
writing or life. This was active forgetting. Knowledge as object, as something
that was owned, as body of known facts, traditions and laws was mostly a
burden as long as the rebel was not able to absorb and transform it into deed—
something that was a proof of his sovereignty.
201
202
203
between author and reader and the discontinuity in the process of communication implied by
the interaction of egotists.
Ruest saw in Schiller a proto-anarchist. Schiller understood philosophy not as an accumulation of knowledge but as permanent revolt. “Schiller unser Schiller, der Tell-Schiller:
war Anarchist” (124).
“Glaubt keinem großen Manne mehr […], glaubt Euch selbst und reißt die Augen auf” (122).
“Das Wissen selbst muss sterben, um im Tode wieder aufzublühen, als Wille” (125).
94
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
Intellectuals, philosophers and educators, that is, the agents that administered
this body of knowledge, often forgot that texts existed to serve the singularity
in its quest of “becoming what it was” and advocated the memorization and
reproduction of knowledge.204 Ruest called for revolts in the schools where
teachers taught obedience and in communities where intellectuals or philosophers
arrested the future with their universalizing discourses. He was contemplating a
new era that followed the failed “project of the Enlightenment” and the capitalistdemocratic state, with their pillars in private property, education, a limited version
of individual freedom, religious belief, and ethics of work. These practices needed
to be discarded in order to allow the return of free thought.205 Ruest envisioned
a leap from the era of the spectacle of knowledge, thought and abstraction (the
“Denkperiode”) into a time of post-knowledge, post-philosophy and singular
thought (125). True intellectual practice was not manipulation of concepts but
revolt and singularization.206
Authority
It was not unusual for individualist anarchists to explain their rapport with
the author of Der Einzige und sein Eigentum. After all, they needed to justify a
certain form of proselytism. In his book on Stirner, Mackay also tackled the issue.
Mackay came up with a simple answer. Stirner himself had already solved the
problem of authority. Authority had been undermined within the signifier itself.
Stirner’s style was undoing the master-disciple relationship, so Mackay needed
not worry about the way in which he adopted Stirner’s concepts. Stirner’s writings
were not systematic but fragmentary, and they were not written to persuade but
to inspire autonomous thinking. Stirner did not rely on an inflammatory rhetoric,
as Nietzsche did, but expressed himself in a dry, informative, and sometimes
204
205
206
Might 1919 be the year of the death of the intellectual/ philosopher? “Dreimal schmisset Ihr
‘raus, dreimal nahmt Ihr Euch Universallehrer, 1789, 1848, 1873—dreimal bekam Euch der
Bakel wieder! Zum vierten Mal—: 1919?” (123).
A return to “den Mutterschoß der Erde […], damit eine neue Freiheit, die des Willens, von
ihren edelsten Säften sich nähre” (125).
“Vielmehr, ist die höchste Praxis die, dass ein freier Mensch sich selbst offenbart, und das
Wissen, das zu sterben weiß, ist die Freiheit, welche Leben gibt” (125).
95
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
ironic tone that prevented the reader from identification.207 For Mackay, Stirner
did not call for proselytizing. He was an egotist writing for other egotists. He
did not speak with the superiority of a priest, as the mouthpiece of some god or
grand idea. He left posterity his words to do what they pleased with it. He wrote
primarily for himself and for the joy of writing, and not considering an audience,
which he wanted to persuade. He was not responsible for his words in front of
his readers and his readers had also no duty to obey, respect or adore them.208
Ruest and his colleagues were more scrupulous than Mackay. Ruest discussed
his relationship with Stirner in “The Last Revolution.” For Mackay, the issue of
authority was solved by the rhetoric of Stirner’s writing. Ruest, however, did
worry whether he was behaving like a disciple and whether he had allowed
Stirner’s concepts to control his thought. He also wondered whether he turned
Stirner into a philosophical Messiah. Ruest came up with the following answer,
which was perhaps not the most inspired, but at least testifies to the effort of
anarchists to outline modes of non-authoritarian intellectual cooperation and to
disentangle intellectual affinity and admiration from obedience and control.
Ruest considered that he wrote inspired by the “light” that Stirner had thrown
upon him. He did not follow; he only entered Stirner’s intellectual galaxy, his
Gedankensphäre (2), and used it for his interests. His relationship to Stirner
was one between two egotists. This was made possible not only by Stirner’s
style, but also by the fact that Ruest did not let Stirner’s authority possess his
mind. He was continuously rebelling, and his readers should do the same. “What
the hell, become your own followers,” he pep-talked his readers (3). “Oppose
much, and belong less” (61).209
Mackay’s thesis that authority could be sufficiently undermined by “style”
was unsatisfactory for Ruest. The latter understood that language was authority,
and that it took more than fragmentary writing to dismantle it. One needed to read
disobediently, and refrain from letting oneself hypnotized by the organizing
207
208
209
In fact, this was one of the main reasons why Mackay did not regard Nietzsche as a follower
of Stirner, as so many individualist anarchists and the editors of Der Einzige did. Nietzsche’s
passionate style betrayed eagerness to educate and to create apostles (Mackay Max 18-19).
“Er überlässt es uns, Das, was er sagt, zu glauben oder zu verwerfen […] Er spricht kaum
von uns; kaum dass er zu uns spricht. Er spricht von sich und immer nur von sich. […] Er
that, was er gethan, für sich, weil es ihm Freude machte. Er fordert keinen Dank und wir
schulden ihm nichts.” John Henry Mackay, Max Stirner, 150-151.
“Widersetzt Euch viel; gehört wenig.” This is the title of one of Ruest’s articles.
96
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
power of a text. Respect for the text was damaging to the reader. The anarchist
paradigm was one of abuse. Communication between egotists was an act of mutual
theft, use, mis-use, ab-use for the sake of one’s own interests.
Intellectuals in Times of Turmoil and Confusion
The egotist argument against the authority of the intellectual was not only
backed by theory, but also by an actual historical predicament. Der Einzige’s
premise was that 1919 was a time of utter bewilderment, and as such this time
placed a question mark on intellectual authority. If the human mind had been so
abused by state and war propaganda, who had the right to claim epistemological authority in 1919? If subjects lived in hallucinating times, who had the
legitimacy to universalize? Who could and dared to be the next Hegel? Who had
the right to talk about Geist and the end of history in an era in which one’s sense
of self, one’s values, truths, hopes, and dreams had been so violently confused?
The answer was, of course, nobody. On the other hand, a certain degree of
authority and “pedagogy” were expressed in the pages of Der Einzige. Ruest and
Friedlaender/ Mynona understood that pretending to speak without authority
was an ideal as fake as that of a traditional philosopher’s claim to speak in the
name of the universal.210 The authority residing in language was practically
insurmountable. In spite of their efforts to theorize against authority, to incite
readers to disobedience, and to use a certain self-deconstructive style, the medium
that they were using, language, remained the instrument of order, organizing and
conveying commands.
In the context of mass communication, their position as editors was of course
also one that implied authority. They understood that, although they were fighting
statist propaganda, they were, at the same time, caught in the practices of universal
complicity and generating power. It was pure cynicism to believe that things
could be totally different. This more “constructive” approach surfaced in the
later issues of the journal after starting the Bund. An article written together by
Ruest and Friedlaender/ Mynona in May 1919 synthesized this new tactics
210
This can be another reason why the editors of Der Einzige never recommended themselves
as anarchists. They never assumed the authority of speaking without authority and called
themselves individualists or egotists.
97
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
(“Und zum Vierten Mal: Revolution – ein Schulprogramm” 136-139211). Ruest
and Friedlaender/ Mynona conceded that Der Einzige was also committed to
“educate.” The authors referred to Der Einzige as an emanation from egos for egos,
but did not hide the fact that they understood that they were universalizing too,
and that this practice was problematic. Making concessions to their initial antimobilizing intransigence, Ruest and Friedlaender/ Mynona acknowledged the
necessity of a transitional phase, in which some propaganda as anti-propaganda
was necessary. The objective: until singularities can function in their own language
(139).212
The pedagogy that Ruest and Friedlaender/ Mynona referred to was, however,
anything but dogmatic. They employed a broad set of modifiers to indicate its
non-authoritarian character.213 As in the case of their politics, which was not
mythological because it was based on the interruption of myth, their view on
knowledge and on the role of the intellectual returned to Stirner’s anti-essentialist
position. Knowledge was construed of as built upon nothing, and this nothing
guaranteed that every edifice of knowledge was, at any moment, susceptible of
falling apart.
To break the continuum of authority, contributors to Der Einzige used explicit
calls on the reader, asking them not to obey and not accept uncritically what
was just being argued. Gerhard Lehmann, for example, fractured the argument
of his piece “Apologetisches” with the following remark: “if you want to follow
me, do it; if not, don’t.”214 Ruest asked his readers to relate to texts as egotists.
He himself was one. He followed his interests. He wrote about a world as he
saw it and about how he wanted it to become. Nobody had to follow him. There
were imperatives, desire and subjection in his sentences. Readers should not
obey. Ruest was both subject and object of the universal brainwashing of 1919.
Readers should take only what they pleased, because they were egotists, too. In
an anarchist journal, there could be no principle of authority for them to respect:
not even property of ideas, not even accuracy or truth. In the same way, Ruest
or any other editor of Der Einzige did not feel responsible in front of their readers
211
212
213
214
It bears the same title as Ruest’s article that I discussed above.
“Bis wieder Alle, Allen und in ihrer Sprache wieder verkehren können.”
They regarded it as “füßige, widerspruchsvolle, nie erstarrende Richtmöglichkeit, Selbstregulierbarkeit
aller Lehren, Meinungen, Erfahrungen zu diesen einzigen Sinn und Zweck wieder, welcher –
Das Leben heißt” (139).
“Wenn ihr mir folgen wollt, dann tut’s, wenn nicht, lasst’s bleiben” (65).
98
3. Concepts, Intellectuals, Disobedience
for what they wrote. Why should there be a “respectful” way of handling a text?
Individuals were to interact without normative or institutionalized control.
Der Einzige’s effort to create a climate of writing without authority and egotist
reading was an effort to break with what Jacques Rancière would later call, in
The Ignorant Schoolmaster, the order of explication. The order of explication
organized and limited production of meaning. It imposed the “authority of the
author,” and welded signified and signifier into a whole. Thus, it became instrumental in keeping individuals in a state of mental inferiority and dependency on
explicators.
By positing the discursively uncontainable, yet concrete singularity, Der
Einzige developed an anti-pedagogical pedagogy. This pedagogy countered the
ontological humbling of the singularity on which the state and all institutions of
control were built: the assumption that one’s thoughts and deeds were imperfect
and that they needed a superior agency, like God, the State, the School, Art, or
the Intellectual, to compensate for their inferiority. This pedagogy thus aimed at
fostering the growth of an autonomous and un-humbled being, and an understanding of singularity beyond master-narratives of lack.
Der Einzige’s pedagogy promoted a radically democratic understanding of
reading. Symbols were not only tools of organization and transmission, but also
stimulators, provokers of one’s singular creativity. They were built on nothing,
on an absence of meaning that placed knowledge in the hands of the individual
reader. The journal tried to break apart the “hierarchical world of intelligence”215
by demonstrating that “there is nothing beyond the written page, no false bottom
that necessitates the work of another intelligence, that of the explicator” to
clarify things.216
The culture of disobedience assumed equality between its readers. Since
meaning belonged to everybody and since egotists could plunder texts and build
meaning autonomously, a process of radical emancipation was posited that was
oblivious to dogmas or transcendent authority. This emancipation did not offer
a key to knowledge but a different understanding of it: “to know that no one is
born with more intelligence than his neighbor.”217 Emancipation was the consciousness of this equality.
215
216
217
Jacques Rancière, The Ignorant Schoolmaster, 8.
Jacques Rancière, The Ignorant Schoolmaster, 10.
Jacques Rancière, The Ignorant Schoolmaster, 71.
99
CHAPTER 4
The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism
and the Grotesque
Ulk
Though printed together, Der Einzige and its Beiblatt did not build a unity.
One could envision their relationship as one of mutual interruption. It was a
solution for the different philosophical standpoints of the editors. Ideological
consensus (unity) was in fact not sought. Der Einzige regarded itself as an
intervention against unity. Within Der Einzige’s take on rebellion, interruption
played a central role. One part rebelled against each other; the parts rebelled
against the whole, and the singular against its appropriation by the collective.
Difference was the “deal” behind the Ruest-Friedlaender/ Mynona collaboration.
For some time, their conflicting individual positions intertwined. Friedlaender/
Mynona would experiment with the individualist anarchism framing of his work;
and Ruest would tolerate the questioning of his theses and cohabitate with
Friedlaender/ Mynona’s growing post-World War I essentialist path.218 At this
time, both editors reached the peak of their popularity. The idea of Beiblatt seemed
to be something they both agreed on as a temporary collaborative. The project
originated in their radical background. According to Exner, the supplement carried
out the bohemian imperative to laugh “at all forms of political, scientific, religious,
and also literary and cultural power and authority.”219
The Beiblatt published grotesque fiction and poetry, and its textual strategies
were inspired by the Scheerbartian thesis that power can be laughed into irrelevance.
The first Beiblatt, titled Der Exkaiser, already expressed this stance. Besides carrying
a motto by Stirner that championed for caricaturing high thoughts and values as
a practice of and for the sovereign singularity, the supplement published texts that,
218
219
Friedlaender/ Mynona published just a few articles in the main section. They were all signed
“Dr. S. Friedlaender.” He contributed a piece of fiction for every Beiblatt, all signed “Mynona.”
Lisbeth Exner, Fasching als Logik, 180.
100
4. The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism and the Grotesque
in terms of both form and content, aimed at exposing power and its mechanisms
to irony and ridicule. As the heading suggested, the main target was the monarchy,
whose return many a German politician of the early Weimar days, Ebert included,
was still envisaging. Friedlaender/ Mynona and Scheerbart’s pieces made sure to
portray this possible return as an outrageous relic in the history of human selfoppression.
“The Well-Tanned Flee: A Rococoterie by Mynona” (Der gut bronzierte
Floh. Eine Rokoketterie von Mynona) (8-9) depicted in racy and absurdist colors
the manners of the royal entourage, employing humor to stimulate readers to
contemplate with disobedient eyes the spectacle of power, and question themselves
as spectators and the legitimizing effect of their spectatorship. Scheerbart’s
contributions, one suggestively titled “Laughter is Forbidden” (Das Lachen ist
Verboten) (10-11), also drew on the grotesque to plunder oppressive institutions
of their legitimacy. In this last piece, the twelve kings of the world do not allow
their subjects to laugh while watching court ceremonials. Harsh punishment awaits
the non-compliant. Scheerbart highlights the disciplining effect of committed
and serious spectatorship. Only in a serious world and in front of dedicated eyes,
organized power can perpetuate itself.
Prohibiting laughter thus becomes a preemptive act of controlling the conditions of disobedience. Laughter itself is not disobedience; it is un-identification,
interruption. Laughter is, like growth or entropy, the expression of an ontological
dynamics. Controlling laughter, Scheerbart suggested, constituted an intervention
that reached farther than police repression. Scheerbart’s piece brought to the
fore the tactics of a power that no longer tried to control opinions and actions,
but instincts and life-drives. It was a power that tried to redefine life, and laughter
was one of the means to make life reemerge free from social and political
production.220
220
Laughter and perplexity represented translations of Stirner’s liberating egotistic Frechheit
(impertinence) and of Nietzschean affirmation. For Stirner, Ich “amüsiere mich nach meinem
Geschmacke: je nach meinem Bedürfnis zerkaue ich die Sache, oder ziehe nur ihren Duft
ein” (Der Einzige und sein Eigentum 396). Having a playful attitude towards everything,
toward the “serious” issues, asserts the I as an Eigner. Grotesque laughter was thus a creative
form of forgetting and of interruption both of the self-sufficiency and of the anxiety that
followed the critical act, the radical dismantling of subjectivity performed by Stirnerian analysis.
Grotesque laughter worked both for and against subjectivity; it asserted it as singularity, and
it bewildered it as politically constructed self. It was not an expansive and delirious laughter,
101
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
The suggestion was that intellectual projects, individualist anarchist included,
needed to employ a more complex approach. A theoretical/ philosophical commitment, involving identification with a cause, was not sufficient.221 There was
a need for a double, for a shadow questioning every aspect of the project. This
was the function of the Beiblatt. It was there to present individualist anarchism with
a Janus-face, as a constructive venture and its parody—creation and destruction
of meaning. Together, the two sections of the journal reveal Der Einzige’s double
approach to philosophical issues, as well as its inner dynamics: on the one hand,
the solemn face of the engagement in an existential project, and, on the other,
what Erich Mühsam called Ulk—(to) spoof and make fun of.
According to Mühsam, Ulk was a practice of derision and self-ridicule dear
to the literary bohemia. Ulk complemented daytime intellectual engagement
and militancy with nocturnal subversion. It was more corrosive than “Spaß”
and more profound than “lustiger Unfug.” It negatively challenged or ridiculed
projects, but at the same time, affirmatively, explored the limits of meaning and
asserted alternative logics. It was an exercise in semantic decadence and universal
corruption of values performed in the heretic milieu of the café, at the margins
of the organized world and of one’s intellectual project. At the same time, like
the existential project of the bohemia, it positively experimented with new ways
of bringing together and articulating meaning.
The Beiblatt and its Ulk represented a multiple practice of othering. An
othering that originated in the tension between the literary and the theoretical; an
othering of seriousness through laughter; and an othering that, as interruption
and self-irony, was implicit in the idea of individualist anarchist rebellion.
According to Mühsam, Ulk is “witty self-criticism, robust irony of one’s own
behavior, exaggerated exaggeration of the ridiculous aspects of what one loves;
the checking of the quality of one’s ideals in the test tubes of the grotesque.”
The more one takes life and its problems seriously and is engaged in their solving,
221
but one that “stuck in one’s throat.” This, as it will be argued, is a different notion of both the
grotesque and of laughter than that of Mikhail Bakhtin in Rabelais and His World.
I have showed in the previous chapters the way in which theoretical texts deal with
identification and cause. Philosophical seriousness—as expressed in systematicity, collective
utopias and “revolutionary humanisms”—has already been ridiculed on Ruest’s territory.
102
4. The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism and the Grotesque
the more one needs the gymnastics of Ulk, and keep the one’s psyche in shape
with the help of laughter.222
The second Beiblatt, titled “Der Unmensch,” bearing the same Stirner motto,
published “Will, Will, Will: A Strike of Life by Mynona” (Wille, Wille, Wille. Eine
Lebendigschlagung von Mynona) which was another such example of Ulk-making.
This short story, written for the supplement, occupied its entire printing space.
It intervened “Ulk-wise” in a polemics started in the main section concerning
the “idealist” nature of Stirner’s thinking. There, responding to critics, Ruest
defended the materialist nature of individualist anarchism.223 Mynona’s input
complicated, grotesquely, the Stirnerian-Ruestian premise and experimented
with turning upside-down the latter’s apology. Mynona’s hero could rise above
himself and emphatically transcend the material sphere, kill symbolically his own
body as prison of the soul, and thus exist only as spirit using as many bodies as
he wanted.
Mynona’s piece served as a questioning from an idealist position only in so far
as it entered into a dialogue with Ruest’s piece. In spite of its “idealist”-sounding
plot, Mynona’s story did not convey an outspoken position of its author. It was the
nature of the grotesques to remain ambiguous and aim only at decontextualizing
and recontextualizing ideas. While the spirit bound to materiality was presented as
impotent and eternally incomplete, the “liberated” one grew cruel and tyrannical.
Its disregard for flesh turned into disregard for life, pain and feelings. The soul
without the body was a monster.
“Will, Will, Will” turned upside-down another central concept of individualist
anarchism: revolt. If revolt was understood as disobedience and resistance against
a higher power, be it natural or human-made, Mynona’s story playfully depicted
the anarchist utopia of autonomy as total submission to all the powers that could
dominate the subject, asking whether the impulse behind autonomy was not
sadistic; whether the soul sought anarchy to escape responsibility to the body—
his or her own, or of others.
222
223
“Geistreiche Selbstkritik, robuste Ironisierung der eigenen Gebarung, übertreibende Herauskehrung des Lächerlichen in dem, was man liebt, Erprobung seiner Ideale in Reagenzglas der
Groteske.” Erich Mühsam, “Unpolitische Erinnerungen,” 631, 638. Ludwig Meidner, Kurt
Tucholsky and Otto Erbe praised the bewildering landscapes of Friedlaender/ Mynona’s stories,
and enthused regarding the “Bierulk and the Kabarettfrozzelei” of his subterraneous comic
(in Exner Fasching 337).
I discuss this article in Chapter 2.
103
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
While the example above shows how the Beiblatt complemented as other
and as Jungian shadow the main section, the Janus-face metaphor also sheds light
on the relationship between Friedlaender and Mynona. Friedlaender/ Mynona
regarded his intellectual project in dual terms as well. In the spirit of his polarism,
he conceived of his intellectual self as a split persona: the thinker and the satyr,
the essayist and the author of grotesque pieces, the philosopher-king and the
clown.224 In his autobiography, Friedlaender/ Mynona argues that Friedlaender
invented Mynona as his grotesque scribe. However, the relationship between the
two faces of the mask was, as in the case of the journal, not linear. Ideas did not
simply migrate from the philosophical text to the literary one.225 The philosopher’s
concepts were neither “visualized” nor “tested” in his short stories. Friedlaender/
Mynona kept his two personas apart, estranged, un-reconciled, “de-familiarized.”
Paradoxically, Ernst Marcus, the thinker who converted Friedlaender/ Mynona to
Kantian idealism, advised him to keep a diverging relationship between his two
voices in order to avoid becoming unilateral and dogmatic. Art and metaphysics
should converge on their own in a way that was beyond the power of their
author.226
The Friedlaender vs. Mynona relationship is better documented than the
tensions between Der Einzige and its Beiblatt. It has an explicit philosophical
underpinning in Friedlaender/ Mynona’s pre-war philosophical essays collected
in Schöpferische Indifferenz. Given the ideological tension between Ruest and
Friedlaender/ Mynona, this tension can be extrapolated to the interaction of the two
sections of the journal—at least with regard to the way in which Friedlaender/
Mynona understood his (and the Beiblatt’s) intervention as part of a polar whole.
These texts celebrated a dual construction of experience, and advocated an arrival
at a point of in-difference beyond binary oppositions through a practice of
224
225
226
Friedlaender/ Mynona identified himself as a synthesis of Kant and clown “bizarre Personalunion
[…] von Asket und Lüstling” (Exner, Fasching 29).
Some Friedlaender/ Mynona commentators, like Peter Cardorff, have tried to reconcile the
philosopher with the clown. I have chosen a slash as separator between Friedlaender and Mynona
because, alongside other commentators (Kötz, Exner), I argue that the tension between the two
profiles is more complicated than a simple hyphenation. Here is Kötz: “Mynonas in die Form
der Groteske gegossenen ‘Erzeugnisse des Denkens’ sind keineswegs Ableitungen seiner philosophischen Erkenntnisse, sozusagen populär gemachte Geisteswissenschaft” (Die Prosa 60).
Lisbeth Exner, Fasching als Logik, 320. The parallels will meet in the twenties. It is interesting
how later in his life, that is, after his inner “unification,” Friedlaender/ Mynona does no longer
clearly distinguish between his two personas.
104
4. The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism and the Grotesque
antagonizing contrasts. The point of in-difference constituted the moment of
equilibrium between these diverging binaries.
It was antagonizing and not reconciliation, dialogue or dialectical progress
that lead to the balancing of poles. It was Ulk expressing the tension between the
main part of the journal and its Beiblatt, and the Janus-face metaphor indicating the
relationship between Friedlaender and Mynona. The double face asserted the
singularity of the indefinable whole, escaping discursive mapping as interrupted
construct, as pure present and presence that has overcome binary determinations;
simply put, as creative nothing.
Daimonides
The supplement had few contributors. It mostly included texts signed “Mynona.”
Aside from occasional pieces by Walter Mehring and a series of materials signed
with untraceable pseudonyms such as Tristram Hilarius, Curd Viereck, and Till
Jesuitenjäger, the names that appeared with certain regularity were those of
Daimonides (Karl Döhmann, Dr.) and Paul Scheerbart.
These three main contributors to the Beiblatt belonged to three different
generations. Scheerbart, late romantic and early expressionist, had already passed
away. Mynona was a prominent figure of German modernism. Daimonides was
just emerging with the post-World War I individualist anarchist movement and
the Berlin Dada. Scheerbart was regarded, like Stirner and Nietzsche in the main
section, as a precursor. Mynona, as editor, stood for the present; Daimonides
for the future. The first issue of Der Einzige carried a selection of Scheerbart’s
pieces that helped set a direction for the supplement.227 In subsequent issues,
Daimonides published his “Mynonal-Sonette.”
Daimonides, like Scheerbart, was a member of the pre-war individualist
anarchist inner circle. Mynona’s influence on him was obvious. He published
mainly poems matching the paradox-seeking grotesque of the Beiblatt. Like
Mehring, he was also active in the Dada movement. In his memoirs, Mehring
recalled that Daimonides/ Döhmann was yet another Janus, a highly-educated
227
Titles include “Die Zukunft der exmittierten Potentaten,” “Staats-Photographen” and “Das Lachen
ist verboten.”
105
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
intellectual, initiated in Hindu culture and at the same time a rowdy Dadaist and
bohemian of the Johannes Baader circle.228
Daimonides did not regard his double allegiance as problematic. Dadaists like
Raoul Hausmann, however, did. They separated from individualist anarchism
to move toward more organized and more militant forms of social struggle.
Hausmann, who adopted an overtly hostile attitude toward Der Einzige after Ruest
edited an article he submitted (in order to make it sound more individualist
anarchist than it was),229 qualified Daimonides’s individualist anarchist allegiance
as senile “daimonidale Mynonanie” devoted to ethical laws.230
Daimonides’s style resonated with Mynona’s decadent/ deconstructive approach
to the writing of literature. Using uncanny and grotesque assemblages, his work
contributed to the supplement’s main effort to highlight the normative, subjectivity-producing and authoritarian project underpinning literary conventions.
As Dieter Lehner highlights, his collages of disciplined poetic form, residual
philosophical scholarship and excessive sensuality comprised a rebellious praxis
that focused on the politics of the literary text or, as Lehner puts it, on “on the
continuous disenchantment process of the artistic individual.”231
228
229
230
231
“Ein durchaus seriöser Gelehrter, Sanskritkenner und, [on the other hand], in den Mußestunden,
der ‘Dada-Daimonides’” and Dada-pianist of the circle of Johannes Baader. Dieter Lehner,
Individualanarchismus und Dadaismus, 345.
The article, with the title “Pamphlet gegen die weimarische Lebensauffassung,” was published
in the April 20 issue of Der Einzige (163-4). Hausmann published a response to Ruest’s
adjustments in Die Erde, drawing on an earlier anarchist debate. In 1919, as correspondent of
the anarchist and Dadaist Zurich based journal Dada, he reported on the “boxing match”
between, on one side, Stirner and Friedlaender/ Mynona and, on the other, George Grosz and
Wieland Herzfelde. For the latter, the attack against the cult of individualism (in art) was
aimed at differentiating their projects, like Die Pleite, Der blutige Ernst and later Der Gegner,
from expressionism. Grosz wrote against Friedlaender/ Mynona’s Schöpferische Indifferenz
that “jede Indifferenz ist konterrevolutionär” (Exner Fasching 300). Hugo van den Berg
argues that Friedlaender/ Mynona enjoyed a more positive reception in the Dada circles than
Ruest (Avantgarde 349). Hausmann’s caricature “Dr Max Ruest,” published in Der Dada 2
depicts Ruest as “Stirner’s Hinten.” Hausmann also published a “positive” caricature of Mynona
titled, “Portrait einer alten Frau (Dr. S. Friedlaender-Mynona).”
Dieter Lehner, Individualanarchismus und Dadaismus, 347. Allusion to Daimonides’s “Mynonal
Sonnette” and to one of the titles of the Beiblatt, “Der gestirnerte Himmel.” It is also a
response to Daimonides’s essay, “Zur Theorie des Dadaismus,” in which Daimonides highlights
the individualist-anarchist underpinnings of Dadaism.
Dieter Lehner, Individualanarchismus und Dadaismus, 356, 345.
106
4. The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism and the Grotesque
Mynona
Friedlaender/ Mynona scholars remember his involvement with Der Einzige
for two reasons: first, because the Beiblatt was the place where he published his
novella The Maker (Der Schöpfer); second, because the main section of the
journal hosted Dr. Friedlaender’s piece “Mynona,” which, according to Exner,
was the only theoretical reflection on the grotesque provided by German expressionist literature. Most of the other Friedlaender/ Mynona contributions to the
Beiblatt had already been printed in the pre-war expressionist press, mainly in
Die Aktion and Der Sturm.232 Only “Der Schöpfer,” “Wille! Wille! Wille!” and
“A Lot of Money” (Viel Geld) were new.233 But even Der Schöpfer was not truly
written to be published in Der Einzige. It ended up there because of Friedlaender/
Mynona’s complicated relationships with publishing houses.
I am, however, more interested in the un-original (republished) work that
appeared in the Beiblatt. Being earlier pieces, they tend to be more radical and
less infused with idealism. Moreover, I argue, the choice of republication betrays
an effort on behalf of Friedlaender/ Mynona to experiment—for the last time—
with an individualist anarchist framing of his work, before fully converting to
that which Ruest so much hated, the categorical imperative. By placing his earlier
pieces in the Beiblatt, Friedlaender/ Mynona offered them and, I argue, his work
in general, the chance of a different reading. I suggest that Friedlaender/ Mynona
scholarship profit from this reframing and regard his writings, Schöpferische
Indifferenz included, from a perspective different than that usually employed:
late expressionism, polarism, formalist theories of the grotesque and, most
importantly, the employment of a certain auctorial continuity which leads to the
quest for finding red threads connecting his pre- and post-Kantian conversion
writings. Continuing Dieter Lehner’s analysis—who traced the individualist anarchist
dimensions of Friedlaender’s writings, his pre-war polarism in particular—I
focus on the individualist anarchist potential of Mynona’s grotesqueries.234
232
233
234
“Das weise Raubgetier,” “Der verliebte Leichnam,” “Die Jungfrau als Zahnpulver,” etc.
Libeth Exner, Fasching als Logik, 179.
Lehner calls Friedlaender/ Mynona’s philosophy a synthesis of Nietzsche and Stirner, a philosophy “des vital-selbstherrlichen Individuums” (77). He argues (and I agree with him) that
Schöpferische Indifferenz is much more informed by Stirner than Friedlaender/ Mynona is
willing to admit (75). Lehner’s reading of Friedlaender/ Mynona, however, is not safe from
107
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
My interpretation is that Friedlaender/ Mynona’s participation in the project
of Der Einzige was part of his polarist intellectual practice. It was meant to
critically balance the growing closure of his thought that occurred after finishing
Schöpferische Indifferenz. He apprehended, I argue, that both individualist anarchism
and grotesque fiction were, like Ulk, a necessary gymnastics aimed at warding
off the temptations of dogmatism.235
The titles Friedlaender/ Mynona chose for the supplement testify to his
acceptance of the individualist anarchist challenge. The Beiblatt bore as mottos
long quotes from Der Einzige und sein Eigentum and changed its name with every
issue. It started with antihumanist headings such as “The Unman” (Der Unmensch)
and “The Man Eater” (Der Menschenfresser); it further integrated Stirnerian
spectrology in “The Godly Swineherd” (Der göttliche Sauhirt), “The Unselfish
Mummy” (Die selbstlose Mumie), “The Ideal Spook” (Das ideale Gespenst) and
“The German I-ling” (Der deutsche Ichel). It sometimes addressed directly the
Stirnerian heritage in “The Stirnered Sky” (Der gerstirnerte Himmel), or expressed
the questioning of established philosophical discourse in “The Philosophical
Shepherd” (Der Philoso-Viehtreiber) and “The Belated Ascetic” (Der nachträgliche
Asket).
Stirner’s Der Einzige und sein Eigentum was a critical analysis of state
structures and of the production of the subject in the organized community. It
neither detailed an intervention against them nor explained the practice of
individual rebellion. It only briefly sketched the undepictable utopia of the
“community of egotists.” It was Ruest and Friedlaender/ Mynona’s task to
continue his legacy and provide a positive textual and corporeal example of it.
In a pre-war article, Friedlaender/ Mynona argued that, as genuine follower of
Stirner and Nietzsche, he was able to refine egotism to perfection by giving it a
235
criticism. Van den Berg believes, in contrast to Lehner, that Friedlaender/ Mynona overcame
Stirner’s influence. Yet he notices some similarities: Friedlaender’s use of the concept of
“schöpferisches Nichts,” his skepticism vis-à-vis humanism and his focus on the autonomous
I. For Van den Berg and for most Friedlaender/ Mynona scholars, Friedlaender/ Mynona is,
at this point, already an idealist. He labels Friedlaender/ Mynona’s philosophy as “idealism
without god.” The spirit precedes matter and can determine it. The world cannot be ultimately
known, it is subjective representation; yet god from the skies is dead (350).
David Weir has argued in favor of a rethinking of the Western literary canon of modernism
via the philosophy of Stirner. In his view, Stirner’s radical individualism is one of the main
sources of inspiration for literary modernism and its subjectivist textual tactics (175).
108
4. The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism and the Grotesque
metaphysical basis.236 He developed Stirner’s position in the realm of creative
thought and literary expression by putting them in the service of the production of
the sovereign singularity. As Rüdiger Sanfranski has it, Stirner’s (and Friedlaender/
Mynona’s) thinking is an act of rebellion that aims at achieving the freedom of
pure creative thought.237 For both Stirner and Friedlaender/ Mynona, “thinking,
is creation; one’s thought is the created, and freedom of thought means that the
creator stands before his creation” and is not in any way its captive.238
It is this emphasis on rebellion as creation (and thus on the overcoming of
Hegelian negativity) that connects Stirner’s work with that of Friedlaender/ Mynona,
as well as the hypothesis regarding the nothingness upon which this creative
sovereign singularity is built, which Friedlaender/ Mynona calls “das schöpferische
Nichts.” From this point of view, I argue with Lehner, that Friedlaender/ Mynona’s
work builds a bridge between Stirner and literary modernism, and that the Beiblatt
is an example of such an interface. It is, indeed, a late effort; one that comes after
the followers of Friedlaender/ Mynona’s ideas have already established their own
movements—for example, the Dada groups—and have chosen more organized
forms of political militancy, like Spartacus and the KPD (German Communist
Party). It was not, however, less creative than the Dada publications.239
Grotesque
Friedlaender/ Mynona’s grotesque is the art of conjunction without reconciliation. In the spirit of polarism, it is a practice of producing divergence. It
represents the ontological fracture at the core of each object, a world that is out
of joint, and whose de-centered sliding cannot be contained. It records the traces
236
237
238
239
S. Friedlaender, “Absolutismus,” 162.
“Die Freiheit zum schöpferischen Denken, was bedeutet, dass man sich nicht unter der Gewalt
des Gedachten beugt. Man muss der Erzeuger seines Denkens bleiben.” Rüdiger Safranski,
“Nietzsche. Biographie seines Denkens,” 26.
“Denken ist Schöpfertum, der Gedanke ist Geschöpf, und Freiheit zum denken bedeutet, dass
der Schöpfer über seinem Geschöpf steht; das Denken ist Potenz und darum mehr als das
Gedachte, das lebendige Denken darf sich nicht in die Gefangenschaft des Gedankens begeben.”
Rüdiger Safranski, “Nietzsche. Biographie seines Denkens,” 26.
For Lehner, Mynona is the connecting element between the Stirner Renaissance of the 1890s
and the anarchist aesthetics of the post-WW1 Dadaists like Baader and Huelsenbeck. Mynona
was an educator of the young avant-gardists. His influence was two-fold: first, his grotesques
anticipated the Dada collages/ montages/ experiments; second, his polarist philosophy was a
theoretical starting point for the Dada insurrection (72).
109
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
of a subjectivity that has lost its appetite for identification. Rage, nostalgia and
commitment (piety), the three main affects of unity according to the Stirnerian
logic, are replaced by fascination with perplexity, an addiction to a devilish game
of provoking singularities to reconsider their images, and to respond to their
existential puzzlement with a burst of liberating laughter.
Laughter plays an important role in the literary practices of the Beiblatt, and
differentiates its Scheerbartian direction from other understandings of the
grotesque. Pamela Kort locates this trend in the German art and literature of the
turn of the century. In this place and time, the grotesque becomes less demonical
and more fantastical and comical.240 Laughter is for Friedlaender/ Mynona the
creative principle. It un-essentially constitutes the Ich. Thus it has to be a coarse
laughter, crude, violent, which explodes Differenz and produces singularity, the
undifferentiated self. Thus creation has no logic, no purpose, no commitment,
and no meaning. Laughter, Cardorff highlights, is an antidote against drowning
in the world of differences. It helps one escape it uninjured.241
The grotesque of the Beiblatt can be differentiated from the gothic and the
sublime according to these features. A grotesque text in the service of the sublime
as understood by Kantian aesthetics would contradict the spirit of Der Einzige and
its ethos of empowering readership. Kantian sublime, with its awing religious
connotations, is a presentation that overwhelms the body or the mind and inspires
infinite authority.242 Inspired by Nietzsche’s Zarathustra and his transvaluation
of all values, the grotesque laughter cultivated by Der Einzige expresses the joy
of overcoming “holy” forms of authority to which a construct like the sublime
exposes the singularity. And if this laughter is, as it has been said, a laughter that
“sticks in your throat,” the reason for that should be found in the handicapping
effect of structures of authority on the singularity. By producing the singularity
as human and the self as subject, power turns autonomy into an unconsciously
dreaded state of being.
The grotesque of the Beiblatt, however, should not be regarded as producing
the laughter of the Nietzschean satyr. No doubt, there is Spott (satire) in the
240
241
242
Pamela Kort, “Grotesk: Eine andere Moderne,” 19. Kort studies Scheerbart’s equivalent in
painting, Arnold Böklin.
Peter Cardorff, Friedlaender (Mynona) zur Einführung, 85-86.
Kathrin Kötz highlights that the understanding of the grotesque as opposite to the sublime
was not unknown to Hegel, Kant and Hugo (41).
110
4. The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism and the Grotesque
writings of Scheerbart and Mynona. The latter’s 1919 book project, which he
called an un-novel (Unroman) was titled The Ridge of the Scoffers (Der Bank
der Spötter). On the agenda of the Beiblatt, Spott came always with a twist. It
was not what Kurt Tucholsky advocated as a utopian act of criticism, in which
one regime of truth, beauty and morality was lambasted in the name of another.243
The Beiblatt lacked this second regime of truth designed to substitute the
hegemonic one. A close reading of Friedlaender/ Mynona’s grotesques reveals
that ridicule did not point to a utopia hidden behind the curtain. In the world of
dead gods, satire had to be rethought. Ruest defined Der Einzige as an antidialectical project. Der Einzige emerged from the ruins of the Hegelian world
of the spirit associated with the bloodbath of World War I and in thoughtful
opposition to dialectical materialism.244 The grotesque of the Beiblatt confirmed
this position. Like critique and dialectics, satire, as Tucholsky understood it, was
a “modern” genre. It was a genre of hope and progress, engaged in the enabling
of the transition from one moment in history to another. As in Hegelian dialectics,
satire invested negation with the power to carry on this shift.
In contrast to this “genre of hope,” the Beiblatt’s grotesqueries highlighted
the absence of a collective perfection project or, as Ines Hofmann puts it, they
were, “liberated from thoughts of improvement.” The grotesques of Mynona only
alienated, Hofmann argues, indicating a world in which the subjective was fading
away.245
For Mynona, the grotesque fought for the abolition of all norms, hence also
of the idea of the universalizing norm itself as a means of creating communities.
For individualist anarchists, the Ich was built on nothing; the only norm was my
norm. Any synthesizing transcendence was alien to the singularity and was
regarded as grotesque. Thus, alongside with nothingness, the only other accepted
universal was the grotesque. This may sound paradoxical, but it was a consequence
of Stirner’s ontology. Because the Ich rested on nothing, everything and nothing
could be grotesque at the same time. Everything was alien and ill-formed because
egos constructed representations following a logic that was singular, but was
243
244
245
“Der Satiriker ist ein gekränkter Idealist: er will die Welt gut haben, sie ist schlecht, und nun
rennt er gegen das Schlechte an” (Was ist Satire? 75).
“Gleichsam unter den zusammenbrechenden Trümmern einer seit Hegels Tode unterminierten
Geisteswelt, und im durchdachten Gegensatz zur Weltanschauung des dialektischen Materialismus.”
Sigrid Hauff, “Maßnahmen des Verschwindens,” 93.
Ines Hoffmann, Sinnlichkeit und Abstraktion, 35.
111
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
asserted as intersubjective. Nothing was alien and ill-formed because once
abandoning hope in intersubjectivity and universalism and trying to construct
communities with and within interruption, one developed different faculties of
contemplating the singularity, which were not based on the identity principle.
This dual nature of the grotesque is demonstrated by Geoffrey Harpham in
the opposition between the “religious” grotesque of the cave paintings and the
grotesque ornament of the Renaissance. On the one hand, we have a grotesque
that is synthesizing, that “looks odd” because it tries to produce and assert a
totality. On the other hand, we have a grotesque of the eternal metamorphosis,
of anything goes, that bewilders because it reveals that no synthesis is possible
and because, unlike in dialectics, change emerges without an essential narrative
of history. The singularity’s gaze at these cultural artifacts is also different—one
the one hand, the self-warping gaze of identification, on the other, the perplexed
but at the same time empowering gaze of being singular.
Anarchist thinker John Zerzan criticizes the social practice of art starting
with its origins in the “synthetic grotesque” of the Altamira and Lascaux cave
paintings. His observations are critical for the understanding of the grotesque of
the Beiblatt as an effort to undo established artistic practices and the symbolic
thinking that they involved. Zerzan, like Friedlaender/ Mynona and Der Einzige,
finds the origins of artistic expression in the double effort to overcome the idea
of the eternal present (see Friedlaender/ Mynona’s “Präsentismus”) and to organize
communities by mediating singularity along the ritual of “reading”—that is,
decoding and identifying with symbols. All that is spontaneous, organic and
instinctive is to be neutered by art and myth.246
From this perspective, the grotesque is an effort to destroy the symbolic
order in which art participates. In another essay with a conspicuous Stirnerian
title, “Running on Emptiness,” Zerzan equates the emergence of symbolic thought
with a “restless spirit of innovation and anxiety,” engaged in “continually changing
symbolic modes” and seeking “to fix what cannot be redressed without rejecting
the symbolic order and its estranged world.”247 For individualist anarchism, the
246
247
John Zerzan, Elements of Refusal, 65. Past and future are invented by desire. “It was social
anxiety; people felt something precious slipping away (Zerzan Elements 63).” Art played a
mnemonic function. “Art, with myth closely following, served as the semblance of real
memory” (Zerzan Elements 64).
John Zerzan, Running on Emptiness, 3-4.
112
4. The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism and the Grotesque
symbolic order is the organizing project of modernity. Der Einzige’s critique of
intersubjectivity is derived from the critique of Enlightenment’s emphasis on
education, seen as the effort to build communities through the practice of reading
and symbolic mediation. Its project is, from this point of view, an effort to sabotage
the dialectical fervor of the civilizing process, of overcoming one order by
mobilizing for another.
At the level of literary discourse, Mynona’s grotesques reflect the puzzlement
of a mind that is still functioning under the “old regime” of knowledge, founded
on intersubjectivity, humanism, and universalism. The puzzled mind is the
mind of the enlightener, the mind that looks for the underlying principle, for the
constitutive sign, for a presence where there is only absence. If, however, nothing
is bewildering anymore, and no singularity seems to await closure with regard
to itself and its sovereignty (a closure that, after all, will constitute the pretext
for another dialectical opening in the cycle of “restlessness and anxiety”) then
the work of art loses its ideological function, and a mythic and organizing closure
is not awaited from it anymore.
In the polarist terms of Mynona’s Creative Indifference, the grotesque is an
experience of balancing. A paradoxical image is put together. If a grotesque
effort lacks telos, this absence is not understood in terms of art for art’s sake. The
grotesque is not suspension of direction as in a phenomenological or Adornian
utopia of art. The grotesque is neither the engaged art of the naturalists nor
decadent aestheticism. In contrast to the latter, it does not assert the singular in
an act of circular referentiality. Instead of teleological reduction or the forging
of a pure language of art, the grotesque is a double move of, first, feverishly
asserting life, and second, of tearing it apart, as in a bacchanalia, having it diverge
toward opposites.
The grotesque, however, does neither reconcile nor convey a choice. That
would be all too human. Friedlaender/ Mynona (like Zerzan) argues that choice
(unilateralizing) is the outcome of fear. And because the act of rendering unilateral is repressive, ghosts haunt it, intensifying its horror vacui. If choice is
order cast upon that which cannot be ordered, revolutions are shifts from one
act of rendering unilateral to another caused by the dread of the questions these
ghosts may ask.
Mensch (the human) is the original act of unilateralizing, Friedlaender/
Mynona’s philosophy argues. The effort to overcome humanity has produced
113
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
history—an alienated version of it—and temporality divided between the past
and future and action between negation, dialectics, and progress. This is why
every truly radical rebellion has to be antihumanist. Produced as Mensch, the
singularity cannot live freely, dangerously, without principles, in the Dionysian
feast of balancing poles. The voids and abysses between the poles horrify the
human and cause it to cling to presences and turn them into universal laws.
The grotesque aims at undoing this habitus. Stories without agenda have the
effect of confusing and provoking the reader in unexpected ways. Faced with a
“balanced” structure, readers feel lost and discomforted. This frustration should
thus help the reader realize how dependent he or she is on authority in his or
her encounter with literature. The negative reaction triggered by the balanced
structure highlights the degree to which authority has perverted readers. In fact,
a balanced structure emerges as an exercise in empowerment. However, long
years of discipline have warped the singularity against its desire. The euphoria
of empowerment and autonomy is thus replaced by the frustration of the subject
and its nostalgia for being administered.
The grotesque employs not only the strategies of violent representation, but
also the provocative approach of irony. Irony is instrumental in creating a double
language, in interrupting the auctorial voice, and endowing the text with spectrality.
The double language is the language of the counterposed poles. Irony draws the
reader into the polarist game and reveals that every statement has shadows—
like Janus, two faces. Every statement also means something else, something
that is not specified, but whose existence is suggested. The participation of the
reader as polarizer is needed to produce that other meaning.
Mynona’s fiction employs irony when tackling ethical positions. “A New
Toy for Kids” (Neues Kinderspielzeug) published in the second Beiblatt (Der
Unmensch—with a pacifist theme), provokes the reader by displaying a confusing
complicity with the perverse and the abominable. The story is staged as a talk
given by a libertarian education reformer. In sober language, the reformer suggests
that, in the spirit of truth and realism, toys should more accurately reflect the
deeds of man. Toys should help children explore the action on frontlines, crime
sites, brothels, and politics. Children should not be kept away from the realities
of murder, war, prostitution, and propaganda. It is better to expose them to such
issues at an early age, the reformer argues, because their gaze is not yet perverted
114
4. The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism and the Grotesque
by moral dogmas, and their curious eyes will record facts just the way they are,
as yet another aspect of life.
Placed amidst provoking titles such as “Murder Joy” (Mordsjubel) and
“The Militarism of the Old Indians” (Der Militarismus bei den alten Indianern),
Friedlaender/ Mynona’s piece develops this argument of libertarian child-rearing,
supported by the anarchist movement, to its ultimate consequences.248 It brings
it in a gray zone where every statement becomes spectral, that is, it multiplies
its meanings getting closer to its opposite. The edgy nature of the reformer’s
statements makes his authority crumble, leaving the reader all by himself or
herself to judge his theses (bordering on delirium):
One should introduce blood (obviously artificial), and it will immediately be
more fun for the kids. It is super easy! One should manufacture hollow soldiers
with sieve-like openings. If they tumble over, they spray red-dyed water.249
In the following six paragraphs, the text goes on advising that this play kit
should also include a mass grave, a hospital for the wounded with surgery tables
where amputations could be performed. Games should depict barricades, revolutions,
slaughterhouses, brothels, scenes of arson, robberies, acts of terror, cemeteries,
crematories, famine, asylums for homeless, prisons, and guillotine executions.
But when the reader can finally decide that this disturbing rhetoric is after all
delirious, and that it represents a parody of the libertarian discourse on nonrepressive education, and, consequently, the reader can regard the story as a
satire against the phony morality of Western culture which has distanced itself
physically and morally from the violence on which it is constructed, Mynona
inserts two frustrating last paragraphs that undermine this reading. Even irony
needs balancing. In other words, balancing is never enough, equilibrium is not
perfect, and each final intervention calls for another. So Mynona increases
“confusion” with a twist. Were the arguments of the educator so delirious after
all? Isn’t lying to our children the worst thing we can do? Is this early exposure
really preparing children against phony bourgeois morality? Is false consciousness truly generated by artificial fears and pruderies? Could psychological
248
249
Der Einzige published numerous articles on libertarian education especially in the second part
of its existence.
“Man führe Blut ein (natürlich künstliches!), und sofort macht es auch den Kindchen mehr
Spaß. Das ist kolossal leicht: man verfertige hohle Soldaten mit siebartigen Öffunugen. Purzeln
sie um, so verspritzen sie rotgefärbtes Wasser” (21).
115
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
damage be only a ruse? Shouldn’t parents and educators trust the innate innocence
and amorality of the singularity? Wouldn’t this early exposure teach them to
laugh and own, later, as adults, the tools to become free consciousnesses able to
perform the transvaluation of all values preached by Zarathustra?250
Leafing through the journal, the reader will notice that the theories of the
modern educator connect to theses that are central to the literary project of Der
Einzige: the struggle against organization, against the production of the ethical
and repressed subject, and the Beiblatt’s belief in the liberating power of laughter,
which according to Mynona, should be taught early to all children.251
This story serves also as example of how to tackle the issue of authorship
and authority with regard to Der Einzige. The author Mynona disappears behind
the balanced structure. If the confused reader would like to know “what Mynona
thinks,” he or she cannot find out from this text. Mynona is after all only a
pseudonym, Anonym (anonymous in German) written backwards. Since the God
of the twentieth century has died, so have its authors. The reader should not be
given transcendent guidance—guidance from the author. It’s up to the reader to
decide whether to agree with the libertarian educator or not. In the absence of
a guiding authority, reading becomes an emancipating exercise. If closure is
desired, it lies in the hands of the reader. In front of balanced structures, the
reader can experience his or her autonomy of thought.
Many scholars of the grotesque have emphasized the puzzling effects sought
by this literary genre and its open-ended rhetoric. In Friedlaender/ Mynona’s
case, practicing the grotesque represents a rebellion (complementary to that of
expressionism) against a world that is saturated with knowledge, with answers;
a world dominated by what Kant calls the intellect. It is the paranoia of deductive
thinking that is tackled by Friedlaender/ Mynona’s grotesques like “Neues
Kinderspielzeug.” Expressionist literature employs as alternatives the irrational
and the mystical (following romanticism). What characterizes Mynona’s textual
tactics is not the quest for the irrational as meta-rational, that is, as an alternative
250
251
If the puzzled reader returns to the beginning of the text, he or she will notice that the story
displays a motto from Also sprach Zarathustra: “Aber nun lasst diese Kinderstube, meine eigne
Höhle, wo heute alle Kinder zu Hause sind” (21).
“Dass die Kleinchen über Alles lachen, auch über die Kehrseiten des Lebens, das ist geradezu
die herrliche Ausdehnung der strahlenden Heiterkeit auch über alles was sonst so schnöde
von ihr Verlassene und nur dadurch so Triste. Das ist der Humor, welchem künftige Geschlechter,
so erzogen, nichts mehr vorenthalten werden!” (22).
116
4. The Beiblatt: Individualist Anarchism and the Grotesque
way to institutionalized intellectual activity. Mynona is old-fashioned and his work
also does not seek a leap into another regime of thought, as Tucholsky prescribed
with regard to irony and satire. Mynona looks for no alternative from without,
but tries to interrupt what is from within. He works with the paradox, and his
grotesques compel their recipients to think and rethink the contrasts and incongruences that they take in when they consume texts.252 The higher goal is to
stimulate readers to reuse what they already have: rational language.
“The Vegetablian Fatherhood” (Die vegetablishe Vaterschaft), published in
the supplement The Men Eater (Der Menschenfresser) is such a response to a
world saturated with knowledge. Positivism is already questioned in the opening
paragraphs of the story. Here, Mynona inserts a critique of the binary system of
oppositions and structural limitations (repressions) that this thinking works with.
The discursive grid that the regime of truth casts over nature discriminates between
various aspects of reality and segregates them beyond any recovering connection.
Friedlaender/ Mynona protests to this predicament, commenting that such separations produced as if one had used scissors seem to be the work of pedantic thinkers
going against the nature of things.253
At the center of Friedlaender/ Mynona’s story is the assumption that a rose is
the father of a girl. The world of empirical knowledge cannot, of course, accept
such an explanation. Consequently, it reacts as it always does to what it cannot
understand. It represses it. Using the literary strategy of the fantastic, the story
absorbs into its vortex of absolute questioning the mechanisms that produce certitude
in the world of positive, empirical, ergo unilateral knowledge. Of course, again,
there is no clear message that emerges from the narrative, but one can read it, all
the auctorial practices of deconstruction considered, as revealing how the regime
of truth produces institutions repressing otherness (the paradox of the grotesque
itself), that which they cannot appropriate.254
In his insightful study on the grotesque, Geoffrey Harpham speculates with
Levy-Bruhl and Levi-Strauss that the grotesque functions within the order of the
pre-logical. Grotesqueries “stand at a margin of consciousness between the known
252
253
254
Kathrin Kötz, Die Prosa Paul Ostaijens, 47.
“Überhaupt ist diese wie mit der Schere geschnittene Abtrennung der Wesen das Werk gelehrter
Pedanten, die nicht wissen, dass sie gegen den Zusammenhang der Natur sündigen, wenn sie
trennen, ohne gehörig zu verbinden” (45).
The piece becomes a reflection on the grotesque as the absolute intermediary and an unassimilable
other.
117
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
and the unknown, the perceived and the unperceived, calling into question the
adequacy of our ways of organizing the world, of dividing the continuum of
experience into knowable particles.”255 For Harpham, “grotesque” is a word that
stands for the momentary paralysis of language and signification. The reader is
not able to find the words to describe what he or she sees, which in turn makes
them reflect not only on language and signification, but also on the ideological
and political context underpinning them.
Meaning is being torn apart in grotesque representation, Harpham argues,
and is also radically re-ordered. Readers never settle in the intermediary realm of
the grotesque; they “escape” it by producing semantic closure. Harpham concludes
that this is emancipating. It generates the uncanny intuition of a promise of a
hidden meaning—but only an inkling, only a frustrated, unsatisfied hope. Change
is engendered without authority. Moreover, the anamorphic mechanisms of the
grotesque, described by Peter Fuß as inversion, distortion and mixing (Verkehrung,
Verzerrung, Vermischung), opposing the structure-forming and organizing mechanisms of hierarchization, dichotomization and categorization (Hierarchisierung,
Dichotomisierung, Kategorisierung), emerge rather from an immanent becoming
that functions without principle. These mechanisms work non-dialectically, based
on an immanent power of language to produce difference:
Aligning, discriminating and sorting are the classical Apollonian mechanisms of
morphosis. They face the grotesque-Dionysian mechanisms of anamorphosis.256
The grotesque is thus cause without causality, agency without authority, production
of difference without principle, without an “arche,” that is, anarchical.
255
256
Geoffrey Galt Harpham, On the Grotesque, 3.
“Reihen, Unterscheiden und Sortieren sind die klassisch-apollinischen Mechanismen der
Morphose. Ihnen stehen die grotesk-dionysische Mechanismen der Anamorphose gegenüber.”
Peter Fuß, Das Groteske, 236.
118
EPILOGUE
Individualist Anarchism
in the Twenty-First Century
In this Epilogue, I will briefly discuss resurgences of individualist anarchist
thought of the end of twentieth century and the first decade of the 21st century,
in particular writings from before the 2008 crash. Most of these texts index
movements of the Left that have still not gathered enough momentum to attract
public and scholarly attention. This shows, among other things, that individualist
anarchism still faces problems liberating its discourse from the suspicion that it
feeds concepts to the libertarian Right and that the most important post-World
War II avatar of the Stirnerian singularity is the Randian superhero. All things
considered, progressive, leftist individualist anarchism still awaits a second or a
third Renaissance and insightful reinterpretations of Stirner alongside those of
Todd May and Saul Newman.
Anselm Ruest tried to revive Der Einzige in 1920, 1923 and 1933. These
attempts produced a body of texts, most of them signed by Ruest himself, which
continued the ideas of 1919, but their originality was limited. The Beiblatt was
abandoned and Friedlaender/ Mynona contributed only occasionally. A new Der
Einzige reappeared in 1998, in Leipzig, edited by Kurt Fleming, with no other
connection to the interwar weekly except the fact that it also derived its title from
Stirner’s opus. It appeared in this format until 2006, and then, from 2008 to 2013,
as the publication of the Max Stirner Society (in a more academic context).
The Leipzig version of the journal had as main contributors independent
Stirner scholars such as Bernd Kast, Bernd A. Laska, Ibrahim H. Türkdogan,
Christian Berners, and Maurice Schuhmann. Though not an academic journal,
this new Der Einzige was a Stirner studies publication with limited interest in
anarchism and politics. It appeared three times a year, published usually thematic
issues with titles such as “Max Stirner and Individuality” and “Max Stirner and
119
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
the Marquis de Sade,” and aimed at marketing Stirner’s thinking to philosophy
readers. The same goals were followed by the 2008-2013 series.257
The Stirner-inspired individualist anarchist tradition is continued by another
German journal, published in Hamburg, titled espero. Forum für libertäre Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsordnung (Forum for libertarian social and economic order).
It is the monthly of the Mackay-Gesellschaft and is edited by Uwe Timm und
Jochen Knoblauch. The polemic anarchist direction of the journal is highlighted
in the self-promotional blurb “espero remains a nonconformist journal that
addresses issues and themes that are tabooed and ignored by the media, parties,
and unions.”258
Stirner’s ideas also inform the US-inspired German postanarchist group
postanarchismus.net. Authors like Jürgen Mümken and Jörg Ulrich continue the
work of Hakim Bey, Todd May and Saul Newman, trace the commonalities of
anarchism and poststructuralism and re-read anarchist texts as an addition to
post-structuralism’s scarce political output. Jörg Ulrich’s Individualität als politische
Religion (Individuality as Political Religion) deploys Stirner’s antihumanism in
order to re-read the Enlightenment not as a radical process of secularization, but
almost as its opposite, that is as a completion of the project of Christianity. From
a similar standpoint, in his book Freiheit, Individualität und Subjektivität (Freedom,
Individuality and Subjectivity) Mümken presents Stirner as the inventor of modern
anti-essentialism, anticipating the antihumanism of Michel Foucault—an antihumanism posited against the triumph of the secular bourgeois reason.259
US postanarchism (or postsocialist anarchism) combines poststructuralist
and Situationist insights, and sometimes Frankfurt school critical theory. Michel
Foucault is the inspiring figure. He represents for the postanarchist movement
what Herbert Marcuse had represented for the German 1968 generation: a thinker
who never regarded himself as an anarchist but whose concepts, because they
had marked a break with the traditional Left, inspired young activists and intellectuals to reconsider anarchism. Poststructuralist concepts reveal a genealogy of
radical thinking that goes back to Stirner and Nietzsche, ironically confirming
Horkheimer’s end-of-career apprehension that it will be Nietzsche (that is, the
257
258
259
An increase in activity took place in 2006, which marked 200 years since Stirner’s birth.
No. 13, March 2006.
Jörg Ulrich, “Warum die Menschen wollen, was sie sollen.”
120
Epilogue
Stirner in Nietzsche) and not Marx who will have had the greater impact on the
political thought of the end of the twentieth century.
The literature of contemporary US anarchist writers such as Hakim Bey and
Feral Faun expresses this trend. If academics like Todd May and Saul Newman
engage poststructuralism historically in order to highlight its anarchist roots and
to suggest that anarchism could be the source of progressive activism in the era
of biopolitics, postanarchism uses the concepts of poststructuralism in order to
start a new movement that departs from the widespread tactics of traditional
anarchism.260
It is no surprise then that one of the main polemics that divides the contemporary
American (and Western) anarchist scene is that between these newly emerged
individualist anarchists (who have grown up reading Foucault and Derrida, reconsidered Nietzsche and Stirner, and filtered them through Guy Debord and
Raul Vaneigem) and thinkers like Noam Chomsky, representing the “old school”
of anarcho-syndicalists or anarcho-communists, who, due in part to their ties to
the sixties’ student movement, still have their landmarks in Spanish anarchism,
the revolutionary theories of Rosa Luxemburg, and the free-unions movement.
A representative work for this new postsocialist trend is Anarchy in the Age
of Dinosaurs, written by a collective calling itself The Curious George Brigade.
The group uses the metaphor of the dinosaur in order to emphasize anarchism’s
nostalgia about turning into a mass-movement, of becoming “mass-ive.” The
illusion that dinosaur-culture political projects entertain is that they “believe [that]
if they can reach enough mass, through parties, organization and movements [they]
can challenge the master dinosaur [the state/ capital] and tear power away from
it.”261 Against such illusory practices, the collective recommends, like Der Einzige
almost a century before, the rejection of organization, and it envisages revolt
“not as a mass of isolated consumers following established ideologies, but as
individuals creating our own futures.”262
The reproach that this new generation of individualist anarchists directs
against the older one is that the latter had never mustered the courage to push
anarchy to its ultimate consequences: chaos, wildness, play, or nothingness. This is
why a true movement does not need a defined political aim other than anarchy
260
261
262
Saul Newman, Postanarchism.
The Curious George Brigade, Anarchy in the Age of Dinosaurs, 9.
The Curious George Brigade, Anarchy in the Age of Dinosaurs, 23.
121
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
itself: “Anarchy is the name we have given to the arrow aimed at the heart of every
dinosaur.”263
Hakim Bey’s work confers more philosophical depth to this resurgence of
radical anarchism. His texts combine a romantic/ mystic language with the antiessentialist and antihumanist idiom of individualist anarchism and poststructuralism.
He too advocates individual revolt in an era of diffuse and overwhelming biopolitical power that can no longer be “overthrown” by revolutions. Revolutions
can engage only simulacra of the state machine, and, history has shown, these
revolutions end up reproducing organization. Bey’s suggestion is: if collective
rebellion proves impossible, “then at least a kind of clandestine spiritual jihad
might be launched,” which will produce Temporary Autonomous Zones (TAZ).264
Reminiscent of Der Einzige’s emphasis on revolt as existing in the present,
TAZ are areas provisionally liberated from mediation (the law, the spectacle).
The Occupy Wall Street event was perhaps one of the most visible TAZs in
recent history (even if imperfect from an individualist anarchist perspective and
conspicuously temporary). A TAZ replaces “all forms of organization, tactics and
goals,” and dissolves before becoming organized and before the state can crush
it.265 The “movement” that produces these TAZs is called by Bey “immediatism.”
The tactics of immediatism are those of starting “projects that are founded on
nothing.”266 Stirner’s motto, the motto of individualist anarchism, which appears
in quotation marks, is erroneously attributed by Bey to Nietzsche, highlighting
again that Stirner and individualist anarchism are often delivered in a Nietzschean
wrapping.
Another proponent of individualist anarchism in the postsocialist and postanarchist movement is Feral Faun (Wolfi Landstreicher), the columnist of Anarchy:
A Journal of Desire Armed. Faun writes of himself that “I, Feral Faun, became...
an anarchist... a writer... a Stirner-influenced, post-Situationist, anti-civilization
theorist... if not in my own eyes, at least in the eyes of most people who’ve read
my writings.”267 Feral Faun’s theory of the “feral revolution” involves—besides
Stirner’s egotism, Nietzschean wildness and the individualist anarchist challenge
263
264
265
266
267
The Curious George Brigade, Anarchy in the Age of Dinosaurs, 23.
Hakim Bey, T.A.Z, 18.
Hakim Bey, T.A.Z, 101.
Hakim, Bey, Immediatism, 1.
Feral Faun, “The Last Word.”
122
Epilogue
of living dangerously—the diffuse understanding of power in the lineage of
Foucault, the centrality of play and the emphasis on the transformation of everyday
life promoted by Situationists.
The feral revolution has no program. It is adventure, getting “wild.” It is
individual and aims at un-domestication, liberation of instincts and desires, and,
in Stirnerian lineage, at re-endowing the singularity with the existential selfconfidence and self-mastery that he or she has lost with the rise of authority.
“To set up ‘revolutionary’ programs [Feral Faun argues] is to play on this fear
and distrust, to reinforce the need to be told what to do. No attempt to go feral
can be successful when based on such programs. We need to learn to trust and
act upon our own feelings and experiences, if we are ever to be free.”268
The response from the more organized anarchist movement to the rise of
postanarchism has been virulent. It focuses on the danger that awaits radical
movements in “late capitalism”: the apparatuses of power and persuasion transform
the movement into a subculture, isolate or commodify it (turn it into something
“cool”), render its revolutionary edge innocuous, and administer it as a safety valve
for the stability of the system.269 Such a pamphlet against the new individualist
anarchism is Murray Bookchin’s Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An
Unbridgeable Chasm, which dismisses individualist anarchism in the style of
Marx and Engels (The German Ideology).270 Individualist anarchist positions
are petit bourgeois, Bookchin argues. He doubts that individualist anarchist
“counter-cultural” discourses can generate change and true movements if they
eliminate organization from their center. By rejecting strategies and the rational
articulation of goals, counter-cultures are not able to defend themselves against
the seductive nature of capitalism. They will either indulge in generating false
268
269
270
Feral Faun, “Feral Revolution,” 30.
The postsocialist anarchists themselves have acknowledged this threat. Feral Faun offers a
scathing critique of the niche mentality in “The Anarchist Subculture: A Critique.”
Murray Bookchin borrows Marx and Engels’s narrow understanding of self-interest, essentializes
it as personal profit in liberal-capitalist key, and misreads individualist anarchism’s understanding of autonomy as insulation from community and as petty bourgeois “do my own
thing” mentality: “The ego, identified [by individualist anarchists] almost fetishistically as
the locus of emancipation, turns out to be identical to the ‘sovereign individual’ of laissezfaire individualism. Detached from its social mooring, it achieves not autonomy but the
heteronomous ‘selfhood’ of petty bourgeois enterprise” (52).
123
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
rationalizations serving the capitalist order or break up in splinter groups soon
to be crushed by multinational power dinosaurs.271
Bookchin’s reservations are important for the regrouping of the Left in the
twenty-first century in spite of the fact that his pamphlet is overall a superficial
analysis. For example, he does not give credit to contemporary individualist
anarchism to have seriously considered the reservations mentioned above. What
Bookchin’s approach has however in common with my project is that his
critique of individualist anarchism also entails a historical pilgrimage. The time
and place he and I revisit are similar. The actors, however, differ. Facing the
fall of the Left in “ad hoc adventurism, personal bravura […], celebrations of
theoretical incoherence (pluralism), a basically apolitical and anti-organizational
commitment to imagination, desire, and ecstasy,”272 in other words, the overtaking
of the radical Left by individualist anarchism, Bookchin chants an elegy to the
days of Rosa Luxemburg who was murdered just when Der Einzige was starting.
While Marcuse’s experience of German Soviets brought him close to anarchism,
Bookchin does exactly the opposite. He softens the radicalism he has embraced
during the 1960s and, oblivious to the failures of the revolutionary Left throughout
the twentieth century, revisits its beginnings in order to look for answers and
concepts.
To the question Quo vadis twenty-first century Left, the individualist anarchist
answer is “we don’t know,” or, better, “we shouldn’t know,” which has indeed been
embraced, as I mention in the Introduction, by various prominent contemporary
thinkers of the Left. My analysis has aimed at emphasizing that a reading of the
German 1918-1919 period can provide a framework within which one might
discover an answer. Bookchin’s elegy for the “Left that was” suggests that the
old radical Left needs another chance. In the other corner of the ring, postanarchists
believe that the twenty-first century Left should be inspired by the Left’s mavericks.
271
272
Murray Bookchin, Social Anarchism and Lifestyle Anarchism, 67. This critique is not new.
These questions are a mantra for the critics of the 1960s movement. In Die 68er Bewegung,
Ingrid Gilcher-Holtey voices the mainstream negative assessment of the German ‘68 movement.
The German ‘68 did not engender significant changes in German political life because its
eclectic program has not given birth to political organizations. Fluid dis-organized movements
die out once people get tired of revolting. Only enduring organizations like political parties
and NGOs can continue their impulses in “post-revolutionary times.” Ironically, this argument
is internalized by ‘68ers themselves. In Der Bildstörer, Daniel Cohn-Bendit uses it in order to
legitimize his candidacy for the European Parliament on the lists of the German Green Party.
Murray Bookchin, Social Anarchism and Lifestyle Anarchism, 9.
124
Epilogue
The dilemma then is: Shall the Left replay the twentieth century, re-organize,
renew its discourse according to global relations of production and preach
revolution bearing in mind its failures and excesses? Or should it look for a
radically new way of understanding the political: local, dis-organized, amoral,
a-human, rebellious, an-archic (without ultimate principles), disinterested in
producing sovereign bodies, fearless of chaos, and with its “Sach’ auf Nichts
gestellt”?
125
Bibliography
Adler, Max. Max Stirner und der moderne Sozialismus. Vienna: Monte Verita, 1992.
Althusser, Louis. Lenin and Philosophy, and Other Essays. New York: Monthly
Review Press, 1972.
Aristotle. The Politics. London: Penguin Books, 1992.
Aschheim, Steven E. The Nietzsche Legacy in Germany. 1890-1990. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1992.
Bab, Julius. Die Berliner Bohème. Paderborn: Igel, 1996.
Bakhtin, Mikhail. Rabelais and His World. Bloomington: Indiana University Press:
1984.
Bakunin, Mikhail Aleksandrovich. God and the State. New York: Dover Publications,
1970.
Bartsch, Günter. Anarchismus in Deutschland. Band I 1954-65. (1972) Band II
(1965-1973) and Band III. Dokumentation (1973). Hannover: Fakelträger.
Bäumer, Ludwig, et al. “Aufruf der Antinationalen Sozialisten Partei.” Die Aktion.
45/46, November 16, 1918, 584-586.
Benda, Julien. The Betrayal of the Intellectuals. Boston: Beacon Press, 1955.
Benjamin, Walter. “Der Sürrealismus.” Gesammelte Werke II, I. Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp, 1977, pp 295-310.
Berg, Hubert van der. Avantgarde und Anarchismus: Dada in Zürich und Berlin.
Heidelberg: Winter, 1999.
Bey, Hakim. Immediatism. Edinburgh, Scotland: AK Press, 1992.
Bey, Hakim. T.A.Z: The Temporary Autonomous Zone, Ontological Anarchy, Poetic
Terrorism. New York: Autonomedia, 1991.
Blumenberg, Hans. Das Lachen der Thrakerin: Eine Urgeschichte der Theorie.
Frankfurt a. M: Suhrkamp, 1987.
Blücher, Heinz. “Verstaatlichung des Menschen oder Vermenschlichung des Staates.”
Der individualistische Anarchist. June 1, 1919. Heft 5 (220-224).
Bock, Hans Manfred. Gescichte des “linken Radikalismus” in Deutschland: Ein
Versuch. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1976.
Bookchin, Murray. Social Anarchism and Lifestyle Anarchism: The Unbridgeable
Chasm. Edinburgh, Scotland: AK Press, 1995.
Brown, L. Susan. The Politics of Individualism. Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1993.
Busche, Jürgen. Die 68er: Biographie einer Generation. Berlin: Berliner Taschenbuch,
2003.
126
Epilogue
Byington, Steven T. “Translator’s Introduction.” Max Stirner, The Ego and Its Own.
New York: Benj. R. Tucker, 1907.
Camus, Albert. The Rebel. London: Penguin, 2000.
Cardorff, Peter. Friedlaender (Mynona) zur Einführung. Hamburg: Junius, 1988.
Chomsky, Noam. On Anarchism. London: AK Books, 2005.
Cohn-Bendit, Daniel. Der Bildstörer. Berlin: edition q, 1994.
Cohn-Bendit, Gabriel and Daniel Cohn-Bendit. Linksradikalismus: Gewaltkultur gegen
die Alterskrankheit des Kommunismus. Reinbeck bei Hamburg: Rowohlt, 1968.
The Curious George Brigade. Anarchy in the Age of Dinosaurs. NC, NP, 2003.
Deleuze, Gilles. Nietzsche and Philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press, 1983.
Deleuze, Gilles. Pure Immanence: Essays on a Life. New York: Zone Books, 2001.
Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari. Anti-Oedipus. Capitalism and Schizophrenia.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. 1983.
Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus. Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press, 1987.
Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari. What is Philosophy? New York: Columbia
University Press, 1994.
Derrida, Jacques. “Differance.” Speech and Phenomena, and Other Essays on
Husserl’s Theory of Signs. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973.
Derrida, Jacques. Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning
and the New International. New York: Routledge, 1994.
Derrida, Jacques. “Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences.”
Writing and Difference. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978.
Dreßen, Wolfgang. Antiautoritäres Lager und Anarchismus. Berlin: Wagenbach, 1968.
Dutschke, Rudi. Die Revolte: Wurzeln und Spuren eines Aufbruchs. Hamburg:
Rowohlt, 1983.
Einstein, Carl. “An Die Geistigen.” Stark, Michael (ed). Deutsche Intellektuelle.
1910-1933: Aufrufe, Pamphlete, Betrachtungen. Heidelberg: Verlag Lambert
Schneider, 1984.
Einstein, Carl. “Intellektuelle und Proletarier oder das System der Entmündigung.”
Stark, Michael (ed). Deutsche Intellektuelle: 1910-1933. Aufrufe, Pamphlete,
Betrachtungen. Heidelberg: Verlag Lambert Schneider, 1984.
Eltzbacher, Paul. Der Anarchismus: Eine ideengeschichtliche Darstellung seiner
klassischen Strömungen. Berlin: Libertad, 1987.
Esposito, Roberto. Persons and Things: From the Body's Point of View. New York:
Polity, 2015.
Exner, Lisbeth, Fasching als Logik: Über Salomo Friedlaender/ Mynona. Munich:
Belville, 1996.
Exner, Lisbeth. “Paul Scheerbart: der Kosmokomiker.” Pamela Kort (ed). Grotesk!
130 Jahre Kunst der Frechheit. Munich: Prestel, 2003, 70-71.
127
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
Exner, Lisbeth. “Mynona, ein gotesker Humorist.” In Pamela Kort (ed). Grotesk!
130 Jahre Kunst der Frechheit. Munich: Prestel, 2003, 128-130.
Fähnders, Walter. Anarchismus und Literatur. Stuttgart: Metzler, 1987.
Faun, Feral. “Feral Revolution. ” Demolition Derby. No.1, 1988, p. 30.
Faun, Feral. “The Anarchist Subculture: A Critique.” (http://www.insurgentdesire.
org.uk/subculture.htm)
Faun, Feral. “The Last Word.” http://www.insurgentdesire.org.uk/lastword.htm.
Fisher, Mark. Capitalist Realism: Is There no Alternative? Washington: Zero Books,
2009.
Flasch, Kurt. Die geistige Mobilmachung: Die deutschen Intellektuellen und der
Erste Weltkrieg. Berlin: Alexander Fest, 2000.
Foucault, Michel. Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, H.L. Dreyfus and P.
Rabinow (eds). Brighton: Harvester Press, 1982.
Foucault Michel. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. New York: Vintage
Books, 1991.
Foucault, Michel. The History of Sexuality. Volume I. An Introduction. New York:
Vintage Books, 1990.
Friedlaender, S. “Absolutismus.” Der Sturm. 1914, Zweites Januarheft, nr. 194/5, 162.
Friedlaender S. “Das Individuum und die soziale Frage.” Die Aktion, 20. December
1913, 1182-1186.
Friedlaender, Dr. S. “Kant und die Freiheit: Nach Ernst Marcus.“ Der Sturm, 11. Heft,
February 1919, 145.
Friedlaender, S. “Noch einmal: Werters Leiden.” Die Aktion, April 4, 1914, 289-292.
Friedlaender, S. “Polaristische Gedanken.” Die Aktion. 27/28, July 8, 1916, 368.
Friedlaender, S. “Polaristische Gedanken.” Die Aktion. 29/30, July 22, 1916, 402-403.
Friedlaender, S. “Polarität.” Der Sturm. Nr 92. January 1912. 732-733.
Friedlaender, Dr. S. “Präsentismus: Rede des Erdkaisers an die Menschen.” Der Sturm,
nr 144/145, January 1913, 253-254.
Friedlaender, S. Schöpferische Indifferenz. Munich: Georg Müller, 1918.
Friedlaender, S. “Wagner und Nietzsche zur Zeit ihrer Freundschaft, Elizabeth Förster
Nietzsche.” Berliner Börsen Courier, Jg. 49, Beilage Nr. 38 v. 24.1. 1917, 5.
Friedlaender, S. “Die Weltliche Theologie.” Die Aktion. January 1, 1913.
Friedlaender, S. “Wissenschaft und Politik: Ein Wort and Werner Sombart.” Die Aktion.
March 14, 1914, 121-126.
Friedlaender, Salomo/ Mynona. Briefe aus dem Exil: 1933-1946. Hartmut Geerken
(ed). Mainz: Hase & Koehler, 1982.
Friedlaender, Salomo/ Mynona. Ich (1871-1936): Autobiographische Skizze. Bielefeld:
Aisthesis, 2003.
Friedlaender, Salomo/ Mynona and Alfred Kubin. Briefwechsel. Hartmut Geerken
(ed). Linz: Edition Neue Texte, 1986.
128
Epilogue
Fuß, Peter. Das Groteske. Ein Medium des kulturellen Wandels. Cologne: Böhlau, 2001.
Geerken, Hartmut. “Nachwort.” Der Einzige. Munich, Kraus Reprint, 1980, 344-348.
Gilcher-Holtey, Ingrid. Die 68er Bewegung. Munich: C.H. Beck, 2003.
Goldman, Emma. Anarchism and Other Essays. New York: Mother Earth Publishing
Association, 1910.
Guattari, Félix. Chaosophy. New York: Semiotext[e], 1995.
Guattari, Félix. Molecular Revolution. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1984.
Guerin, Daniel. Anarchism: From Theory to Practice. New York, Monthly Review
Press: 1970.
Haffner, Sebastian. Die deutsche Revolution: 1818-1819. Hamburg: Rowohlt
Taschenbuch, 2004.
Hardt, Michael and Antonio Negri. Empire. New York: Polity 2000.
Hardt, Michael and Antonio Negri. Multitude: War and Democracy in the Age of
Empire. New York: Penguin Books, 2004.
Harpham, Geoffrey Galt. On the Grotesque: Strategies of Contradiction in Art and
Literature. Princeon: Princeton University Press, 1982.
Hauff, Sigrid. “Maßnahmen des Verschwindens: Die Familien Friedlaender und Ruest
im französischen Exil.” Hartmut Geerken (ed). Maßnahmen des Verschwindens:
Salomo Friedlaender/ Mynona, Anselm Ruest, Heinz-Ludwig Friedlaender im
französischen Exil. Munich: Bayerischer Rundfunk, 1993, 8-27.
Hausmann, Raoul. “Dr. Max Ruest.” Walter Mehring. Berlin Dada: Eine Chronik
mit Photos und Dokumenten. Zürich: Verlag der Arche, 1959, Tafel 22.
Helms, Hans G. Die Ideologie der anonymen Gesellschaft: Max Stirners "Einziger"
und der Fortschritt des demokratischen Selbstbewußtseins vom Vormärz bis
zur Bundesrepublik. Cologne: DuMont, 1966.
Henning, Markus and Rolf Raasch. Neoanarchismus in Deutschland. Berlin: OppoVerlag. 2005.
Herzberg, Guntolf. “Die Bedeutung der Kritik von Marx und Engels and Max Stirner.”
Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie. Jg. 16, Heft 12, Berlin 1968.
Hochheimer, Andrea. Groteske Figuren in der Prosa des 19. Jahrhunderts. Inaugural
Dissertation at the Ludwig-Maximilian University, Munich, 29 July 1996.
Hoffmann, Ines. Sinnlichkeit un Abstraktion: Versuch, einen expressionistischen
Text zu lessen. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 2001.
Holz, Heinz. Die abenteuerliche Rebellion: Bürgerliche Protestbewegungen in der
Philosophie. Stirner. Nietzsche. Sartre. Marcuse. Neue Linke. Darmstadt/ Neuwied:
Luchterhand, 1976.
Huneker, James. Egoists: A Book of Supermen. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons,
1910.
Kaufmann, Matthias. Aufgeklärte Anarchie: Eine Einführung in die politische
Philosophie. Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1999.
129
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
Keben, Georg. “John Henry Mackay und sein Philosoph.” Der Einzige 3/7 August
1999, 21-28.
Kessler, Harry. Diaries. New York: Grove Publishing, 2000.
Kneubühler, Theo. “Die Künstler und Schriftsteller und das Tessin (von 1900 bis zur
Gegenwart).” Monte Verita: Berg der Wahrheit. Berlin: Electra Editrice, Exhibition
of Akademie der Künste, Berlin, March 25 – May 6, 1979, 136-178.
Korfmacher, Wolfgang. Stirner denken: Max Stirner und der Einzige. Vienna and
Leizig: Karolinger, 2001.
Kort Pamela. “Grotesk: Eine andere Moderne.” Pamela Kort (ed). Grotesk! 130 Jahre
Kunst der Frechheit. Munich: Prestel, 2003, 10-24.
Kötz, Kathrin. Die Prosa Paul Ostaijens: Stilistische, poetologische und philosophische
Korrespondenzen mit dem Werk von Mynona (Salomo Friedlaender). Münster:
Waxmann, 2001.
Kreuzer, Helmut. Die Boheme. Stuttgart: Metzler, 1968.
Kruse, Wolgang. “The First World War: The ‘True German Revolution.’” Reinhard
Rurüp. The Problem of Revolution in Germany. Oxford: Berg, 2000, 67-92.
Lachmann, Benedict. “Aufruf.” Der individualistische Anarchist. 15 July, Heft 8.
1919, 337.
Lachmann, Benedict. Protagoras, Nietzsche, Stirner: Platz dem Egoismus. Hamburg:
Verlag der Mackay Gesellschaft, 1978.
Lachmann, Benedict. “Und das Licht…?” Der individualistische Anarchist. 1. 1
April, Heft 1. 1919, 10-20.
Lachmann, Benedict. “Übergangssozialisten” Der individualistische Anarchist. 1
May, Heft 3. 1919, 135-144.
Lacoue-Labarthe, Philippe and Jean-Luc Nancy. The Literary Absolute. Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1988.
Lafargue, Paul. Das Recht auf Faulheit. Grafenau: Trotzdem Verlag und Anares Nord,
1998.
Landauer, Gustav. Auch die Vergangenheit ist Zukunft: Essays zum Anarchismus.
Frankfurt: Literaturverlag Luchterhand, 1989.
Laska, Bernd A. “Den Bann brechen: Max Stirner Redivus.” Der Einzige. Nr 3 (11),
August 2000, pp 17-24.
Laska, Bernd A. “Dissident geblieben: Wie Marx und Nietzsche ihren Kollegen Max
Stirner verdrängten und warum er sie geistig überlebt hat: Ein Versuch über die
philosophische Konsquenz in der Aufklärung.”Die Zeit, 27 Januar 2000, 49.
Laska, Bernd A. “Die Individualanarchisten und Stirner.” http://www.lsr-projekt.de/
msinda.html
Laska, Bernd A. “Von Stirner zu Kant: Gerhard Lehmann” Der Einzige. 4 (12),
November 2000, 5-16.
130
Epilogue
Lehmann, Gerhard. “Stirners Theorie der Reaktion.” Der Einzige 4 (12). November
2000. 35-42.
Lehner, Dieter. Individualanarchismus und Dadaismus. Frankfurt am Main: Peter
Lang, 1988.
Linse, Ulrich. Organisierter Anarchismus im deutschen Kaiserreich von 1871.
Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1969.
Linse, Ulrich. “Der Rebell und die ‘Mutter Erde.’ Asconas ‘Heiliger Berg’ in der
Deutung des anarchistischen Bohemien Erich Mühsam.” Monte Verita: Berg der
Wahrheit. Berlin: Electra Editrice, Exhibition of Akademie der Künste, Berlin,
March 25 – May 6, 1979, 26-37.
Mackay, John Henry. Die Anarchisten. Treptow bei Berlin: B. Zack, 1911.
Mackay, John Henry. Der Freiheitsucher. Freiburg/ Br.: Verlag der Mackay
Gesellschaft, 1982.
Mackay, John Henry. Lieber Tucker: Briefe und Postkarten John Henry Mackays
an Benjamin R. Tucker. Hubert Kennedy and Paul Jordens (eds). Berlin: Karin
Kramer, 2001.
Mackay, John Henry. Max Stirner: Sein Leben und sein Werk. Freiburg/Br: Mackay
Gesellschaft, 1977 (reprint of the third edition 1910).
Marcuse, Herbert. One-Dimensional Man. Boston: Beacon Press, 1991.
Marcuse, Ludwig. Mein zwanzigstes Jahrhundert: Auf dem Weg zu einer Autobiographie.
Munich: Paul List, 1960.
Marx Karl and Friedrich Engels. The German Ideology. Moscow: Progress Publishers,
1964.
May, Todd. The Political Philosophy of Poststructuralist Anarchism. University Park:
Pennsylvania State University Press, 1994.
Mommsen, Wolfgang J. “German Artists, Writers and Intellectuals and the Meaning
of War.” John Horne (ed). State, Society and mobilization in Europe during the
First World War. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Mudde, Cas and Cristóbal Rovira Kaltwasser. Populism: A Very Short Introduction.
Oxford University Press, 2017.
Mühsam, Erich. “Boheme.” Gesammlete Aufsätze. Berlin: Klaus Gihl, 1989, 18-25.
Mühsam, Erich. “Idealistisches Manifest.” Kain Nr. 1, Jhg IV, mid April 1914, 1-8.
Mühsam, Erich. “Unpolitische Erinnerungen.” Erich Mühsam. Publizistik. Unpolitische
Erinnerungen. Berlin: Volk und Welt, 1985, 475-670.
Mümken, Jürgen. Freiheit, Individualität und Subjektivität: Staat und Subjekt in
der Postmoderne aus anarchistischer Perspektive. Frankfurt am Main: Edition
AV, 2003.
Mynona, Graue Magie: Ein Berliner Nachschlüsselroman. Berlin: Fannei & Walz, 1989.
Naake, Erhard. Nietzsche und Weimar: Werk und Wirkung im 20. Jahrhundert.
Cologne: Böhlau, 2000.
131
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
Nancy, Jean-Luc. The Inoperative Community. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1991.
Narcho, A. Stell dir vor es gibt Arbeit für alle und keiner geht hin: Die postindustrielle
Anarchie; das Recht auf Arbeit ist Recht auf Ausbeutung. Berlin: Karin Kramer,
1993.
Negri, Antonio. The Politics of Subversion. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1989.
Negt Oskar. Achtundsechzig: Politische Intellektuelle und die Macht. Göttingen:
Steidl, 2001.
Newman, Saul. From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-Authoritarianism and the Dislocation
of Power. Lanham: Lexington Books, 2001.
Newman, Saul. “Spectres of Stirner: A Contemporary Critique of Ideology.” Journal
of Political Ideologies (2001), 6(3), 309–330.
Newman, Saul. Max Stirner. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011.
Newman, Saul. Postanarchism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2011.
Neocleous, Mark. Imagining the State. Maidenhead: Open University Press, 2003.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Also Sprach Zarathustra. Werke. Kritische Gesamtausgabe
Abt. 6. Bd. 1. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1967.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Ecce Homo. Frankfurt am Main: Insel, 1977.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Morgenröte: Gedanken über die moralischen Veorurteile.
Werke. Vol. 2. Frankfurt a.M.: Ullstein, 1972.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. "On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life." Untimely
Meditations. Trans. R.J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1983. 57-124.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. New York: The Modern Library, 1995.
Pamminger, Harald. “Max Stirner—Ein Gedankenspiel.” Der Einzige. Nr. 3 (11),
August 2000.
Partmuß, Friedrich. “Zur Zeit.” Der individualistische Anarchist. 15 May 1919,
Heft 4, 180-2.
Paterson. R.W.K. The Nihilistic Egoist: Max Stirner. London: Oxford University
Press, 1971.
Peters, Michael. Poststructuralism, Politics, and Education. Westport: Bergin &
Garvey, 1996.
Petersen, Alan, Janice Dudley, Patricia Harris. Poststructuralism, Citizenship and
Social Policy. New York: Routledge, 1999.
Pirisch, Volker. Der Sturm. Eine Monographie. Dissertation at the University of
Hamburg. Germany. Hamburg, 1985.
Pfemfert, Franz. “Soldaten! Kameraden der A.S.P., Freunde der Aktion.” Die Aktion,
45/46, November 16, 1918, 587.
Phelan, Anthony (ed). The Weimar Dilemma: Intellectuals in the Weimar Republic.
Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1985.
132
Epilogue
Rancière, Jacques. The Ignorant Schoolmaster. Stanford: Stanford University Press,
1991.
Riley, Thomas A. Germany’s Poet-Anarchist: John Henry Mackay. New York: The
Revisionist Press. 1972.
Rocker, Rudolf. Aus den Memorien eines deutschen Anarchisten. Frankfurt a. M.:
Suhrkamp, 1974.
Rohrmoser, Günter. Das Elend der kritischen Theorie. Freiburg: Verlag Rombach. 1970.
Ruest, Anselm and Mynona. Der Einzige. Hartmut Geerken (ed). Munich: Kraus
Reprint, 1985.
Ruest, Anselm. Max Stirner: Leben- Weltanaschauung Vermächtnis. Berlin: Hermann
Seemann Nachfolger, 1907.
Ruest, Anselm. Zum wirklichen Ich: Prolegomena zum Personalismus. Bielefeld:
Aisthesis, 2004.
Rürup, Reinhard. “Die Ideologisierung des Krieges: ‘Die Ideen von 1914.’” Helmut
Böhme and Fritz Kallenberg (eds). Deutschland und der Erste Weltkrieg. Darmstadt:
Technische Universität, 1987, 121-141.
Sanfranski, Rüdiger. “Nietzsche. Biographie seines Denkens.” Der Einzige. Nr 4(16)
November 2001, pp. 23-27.
Schrift, Alan D. Nietzsche’s French Legacy: A Genealogy of Poststructuralism. New
York: Routledge, 1995.
Schröder, Hans Christoph. “Die deutsche Arbeiterbewegung im Ersten Weltkrieg.“
Helmut Böhme and Fritz Kallenberg (eds). Deutschland und der Erste Weltkrieg.
Darmstadt: Technische Universität, 1987, 121-141.
Senft, Gerhard. “Max Adler und Max Stirner.” Max Adler. Max Stirner und der
Sozialismus, Vienna: Monte Verita, 1992.
Senft, Gerhard. Der Schatten des Einzigen. Vienna: Monte Verita Verlag, 1988.
Seywald. Aiga. Die Presse der sozialen Bewegungen: 1918-1933. Essen: Klartext, 1994.
Steiner, Rudolf. “Max Stirner.” Das Magazin für Literatur. 67. Jg., Nr. 26. Berlin und
Weimar, 2. Juli 1898, 601-605.
Stirner, Max. Der Einzige und sein Eigentum. Stuttgart: Philipp Reclam, 1972.
Stourzh, Herbert. Max Stirners Philosophie des Ich. Berlin: Gebrüder Paetel, 1926.
Streeck, Wolfgang. How Will Capitalism End? Essays on a Failing System. New York:
Verso, 2016.
Strobel, Georg. W. “Die internationale Arbeiterbewegung und der Erste Weltkrieg.”
Helmut Böhme and Fritz Kallenberg (eds). Deutschland und der Erste Weltkrieg.
Darmstadt: Technische Universität, 1987, 121-141.
Szittya, Emil. Das Kuriositäten Kabinett. Konstanz: See, 1923.
Taylor, Seth. Left-Wing Nietzscheans: The Politics of German Expressionism. 19101920. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1990.
133
Constantin Parvulescu The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
Tucholsky, Kurt. “Was ist Satire?” Gesammelte Werke. Bd. 1. 1907-1918. Reinbek
bei Hamburg: Rowohlt, 1975.
Undo, A. “Impertinentismus.” Die Aktion. 35/36. September 4, 1915, 448-450.
Ulrich, Jörg. Individualität als politische Religion: Theologische Mucken und metaphysische Abgründe (post)moderner Subjektivität. Albeck bei Ulm: Verlag Ulmer
Manuskripte, 2002.
Ulrich, Jörg. “Warum die Menschen wollen, was sie sollen: Jürgen Mümken analysiert den Herrschaftscharakter postmoderner Subjektivität und Individualität.”
http://www.postanarchismus.net/index.htm
Ward, Colin. Anarchism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2004.
Weber, Franz-Josef. “Nachwort.” Ernst Pauly, Café des Westens. Hannover: Postskriptum,
1988, I-XXX.
Weir, David. Anarchy and Culture. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1997.
Winkler, Heinrich August. “Revolution by Consensus? Germany 1918-1919.” Reinhard
Rurüp (ed). The Problem of Revolution in Germany. Oxford: Berg, 2000, 93-107.
Wittkop, Justus Franz. Michail A. Bakunin. Hamburg: Rowohlt, 1974.
Zerzan, John. Elements of Refusal. Second edition. Columbia: Paleo Editions, 1999.
Zerzan, John. Running on Emptiness. The Pathology of Civilization. Los Angeles:
Feral House, 2002.
Zima, Peter. “Von Hobbes zu Stirner: Mensch, Naturzustandt und Staat.” Der Einzige.
4 (28), November 2004, 4-9.
Zinn, Howard. A People’s History of the United States. New York: HarperCollins, 2003.
Žižek, Slavoj. Living in the End Times. New York: Verso, 2011.
134